Skip to main content
  • Research article
  • Open access
  • Published:

Experts’ moral views on gene drive technologies: a qualitative interview study

Abstract

Background

Gene drive technologies (GDTs) promote the rapid spread of a particular genetic element within a population of non-human organisms. Potential applications of GDTs include the control of insect vectors, invasive species and agricultural pests. Whether, and if so, under what conditions, GDTs should be deployed is hotly debated. Although broad stances in this debate have been described, the convictions that inform the moral views of the experts shaping these technologies and related policies have not been examined in depth in the academic literature.

Methods

In this qualitative study, we interviewed GDT experts (n = 33) from different disciplines to identify and better understand their moral views regarding these technologies. The pseudonymized transcripts were analyzed thematically.

Results

The respondents’ moral views were principally influenced by their attitudes towards (1) the uncertainty related to GDTs; (2) the alternatives to which they should be compared; and (3) the role humans should have in nature. Respondents agreed there is epistemic uncertainty related to GDTs, identified similar knowledge gaps, and stressed the importance of realistic expectations in discussions on GDTs. They disagreed about whether uncertainty provides a rationale to refrain from field trials (‘risks of intervention’ stance) or to proceed with phased testing to obtain more knowledge given the harms of the status quo (‘risks of non-intervention’ stance). With regards to alternatives to tackle vector-borne diseases, invasive species and agricultural pests, respondents disagreed about which alternatives should be considered (un)feasible and (in)sufficiently explored: conventional strategies (‘downstream solutions’ stance) or systematic changes to health care, political and agricultural systems (‘upstream solutions’ stance). Finally, respondents held different views on nature and whether the use of GDTs is compatible with humans’ role in nature (‘interference’ stance) or not (‘non-interference stance’).

Conclusions

This interview study helps to disentangle the debate on GDTs by providing a better understanding of the moral views of GDT experts. The obtained insights provide valuable stepping-stones for a constructive debate about underlying value conflicts and call attention to topics that deserve further (normative) reflection. Further evaluation of these issues can facilitate the debate on and responsible development of GDTs.

Peer Review reports

Background

Gene drive technologies (GDTs) are genome editing technologies that promote the rapid, progressive spread of a particular genetic element within a population of non-human organisms. Whereas a given gene is passed on to approximately half of an organism’s offspring in normal Mendelian inheritance, gene drives can promote the biased inheritance of a particular gene, so that this gene is passed on to most or even all of an organism’s offspring.Footnote 1 If organisms reproduce quickly, the edited trait can consequently spread rapidly and permanently across the population [1]. In the past few years, GDTs have advanced substantially, from a largely theoretical proposal to proof-of-concept experiments in various organisms [2, 3]. While a number of natural and synthetic gene drive systems based on different molecular mechanisms exist [4], the gene-editing tool CRISPR/Cas9 (Clustered Regularly Interspaced Palindromic Repeats/CRISPR-associated protein 9) has led to particularly significant advancements in GDTs [2]. Gene drives are now “on the horizon” [1].

GDTs have been proposed as a potential strategy to address several major problems, including the burden of vector-borne diseases such as malaria [5], the agricultural, economic, and environmental damage caused by invasive species [6], and the rise of pesticide and herbicide resistance in agricultural settings [7]. Additionally, GDTs could be used in basic research, for example to construct animal models of human disease [8]. Various types of gene drive designs have been proposed, ranging from self-sustaining gene drives which are designed to spread throughout all populations of a species, to self-limiting or thresholded gene drives that are spatially or temporally limited in their spread [1].

The development and possible use of GDTs has stirred considerable scholarly debate. Major concerns in this debate relate to biosafety and biosecurity issues, including the safeguarding of laboratory experiments with GDTs and potential negative effects on ecosystems due to unintended consequences or misuse of the technology [9, 10]. Several papers have mapped the ‘ethical landscape’ and explored various ethical aspects related to GDTs [11, 12]. Other authors have analyzed specific concerns with regard to these technologies, including objections pertaining to 'playing God' and the presumed intrinsic wrongness of tampering with nature [13], intergenerational equity issues [14] and issues related to decision-making about these technologies [15,16,17]. Finally, various guidelines [1, 18,19,20,21], consensus statements and workshop reports [22,23,24,25,26,27] on the scientific, ethical, social, legal and policy implications of GDTs have been published.

A key question in the debate on GDTs is whether—and if so, under what conditions—GDTs should be deployed, with different organizations and stakeholders taking diverging stances. On one side of the spectrum, parties stress the potential of GDTs and argue this provides a strong argument to develop these technologies. These organizations and stakeholders mostly advocate a phased testing approach in which GDTs are investigated in a step-wise manner: first in laboratory studies, then in small-scale, confined field experiments, followed by open small-scale releases and finally large-scale field releases [1, 18, 28]. On the other side of the spectrum, others contend these technologies are too risky or ethically impermissible on other grounds, and argue in favor of a moratorium on field applications of GDTs [29,30,31]. Whilst the stances of particular organizations and stakeholders [3, 22, 32, 33] as well as a range of ethical and governance issues related to GDTs [1, 11,12,13,14,15,16,17, 25] have been identified and described in the literature, the convictions that inform the stances of a wide range of GDT experts have not yet been examined in depth.

Qualitative interviews are a valuable method to identify, better understand, and juxtapose people’s moral views; they can improve the understanding of ethical implications of a technology by providing insights into how interviewees view and weigh different ethical aspects [34]. In this study, we therefore aimed to investigate the moral views of gene drive experts working in various disciplines through a qualitative interview study. We considered it particularly relevant to study the moral views of experts that are actively involved in (the debate on) GDTs, as they are likely to shape these technologies and influence related policymaking. Technological development and related policymaking are human processes; they are not neutral, but rather influenced by the attitudes, convictions and values of those that shape these technologies and the debates about them [35, 36]. By providing insight into the moral views of gene drive experts and linking our results to the previously published literature, this analysis intends to facilitate a more informed and reflected debate on these disputed technologies, and in turn hopes to contribute to their responsible development.

Methods

We performed a qualitative interview study to investigate the moral views of gene drive experts from a variety of disciplines. The study is reported in accordance with the consolidated criteria for reporting qualitative studies (COREQ) [37].

Participant selection and recruitment

Professionals were considered eligible for inclusion in the study if they had contributed to academic publications and/or policy documents on GDT research and development. Eligible participants were identified through a review of the academic [9] and policy publications on GDTs and through so-called snowball sampling, i.e. based on recommendations by previous participants [38]. Based on such snowball sampling, three professionals with broader expertise on respectively global research ethics, anthrozoology (human-non-human-animal studies), and the ethics of gene-editing technologies were also included given the relevance of these fields for the debate on GDTs. To capture a wide range of perspectives on GDTs, a variety of experts from different professional backgrounds and countries were identified. Potential participants were approached and informed about the set-up of the study by e-mail by NG. Recruitment was ended when saturation was reached, i.e. when subsequent interviews no longer brought up new issues (‘coding saturation’) and the formulated themes were sufficiently understood (‘meaning saturation’) [39].

Data collection

Semi-structured interviews were conducted by NG (trained qualitative researcher, female, MA, MD, PhD candidate). In 28 out of 33 interviews, there had been no previous contact between the interviewer and the participant beforehand; in 5 out of the 33 interviews, the interviewer and the participant had met each other prior to the interview in research meetings or a research visit. The interview guide for the interviews (see Additional file 1) was based on an analysis of the ethical arguments related to GDTs that were identified in a previous review [9] and in discussions amongst the research team. The interview consisted of open-ended questions related to potential benefits, hazards and risks of GDTs, stakeholder involvement and governance of GDTs. This article reports the interview findings related to what may be classified as the substantive ethical questions, concerns, and implications of GDTs, i.e. those questions, concerns, and implications that relate to “what is right in terms of duties, rights, and values (..) independent of any decision-making procedure” [40] (p. 155).Footnote 2 The semi-structured design of the study ensured consistency in a number of topics to be discussed by all participants, while also allowing participants to bring up or emphasize particular new issues they considered relevant. Interviews were conducted in English or Dutch and either took place at a location chosen by the participant (for 25 of the 33 interviews), or online via a video conferencing platform (for 8 interviews). An intern (female biomedical science student, BSc) listened to 3 interviews. The interviews were audiotaped, transcribed verbatim, and pseudonymized.

Data analysis

The pseudonymized transcripts were analyzed thematically [41]. An initial coding list was developed based on the topic list, familiarization with the data, and discussion in the research team (NG, KRJ, ALB). Subsequently, NG coded a sample of the transcripts. KRJ critically (re)read this sample of coded transcripts, and the interpretations and suitability of the codes were discussed and compared amongst the research team. The coding list was evaluated and adapted, and all interviews were coded by NG using Nvivo 12 software. The meaning of individual text fragments was determined by interpreting them in the context of the whole interview with the participant in question [42]. In the course of analysis, codes were adapted and additional codes were added to the coding list where necessary. A meaning pattern was identified across the data set, leading to the formulation of interpretative higher order themes. Throughout the process of analysis, the research team went back and forth between the different steps to allow for constant comparison. In the last stage, relevant quotes were selected to illustrate the identified themes.

Results

Out of the 43 experts that were approached, 33 agreed to participate in the study, 8 were unable to participate and 2 did not respond. A total of 33 semi-structured interviews were conducted between November 2018 and July 2019. The interviews lasted between 49 and 114 min, with an average duration of 69 min. 13 respondents were employed in the United States, 11 in the United Kingdom, 8 in various European countries (Belgium, France, Spain, Switzerland, and the Netherlands) and 1 in Burkina Faso. Interview respondents worked in different disciplines, including the natural sciences (n = 11), philosophy/ethics (n = 9), non-governmental organizations (NGOs; n = 5), policy-making (i.e. professionals working in an organization that is involved in designing policy or regulations for GDTs or that funds gene drive research; n = 5) and various social sciences (n = 3). Those individuals who were working in the natural sciences and affiliated with an NGO (n = 2) were classified as ‘natural scientists’.

Three main themes were identified during the data analysis. The moral views of the respondents were principally influenced by their attitudes towards or convictions about [1] how best to deal with the uncertainty related to GDTs; (2) which alternatives should be weighed and how; and (3) their views on nature and the role humans should have in nature. The tables list representative quotations that were selected to illustrate the identified themes. In the following, we indicate the respondents’ disciplines only if it helps to contextualize their opinions in comparison to respondents with different stances.

Theme 1: dealing with uncertainty

Identifying sources of uncertainty

Many respondents stressed the potential of GDTs, yet at the same time reflected on the epistemic (knowledge-related) uncertainty about whether GDTs will be successful at achieving their intended goals. Similarly, many respondents reflected on the difficulty of accurately predicting the potential negative effects of GDTs.

The respondents identified different, interrelated sources of uncertainty. First, some respondents stressed that the proposed applications of GDTs and particular gene drive designs are based on mathematical modeling and limited proof-of-concept studies and are still being developed in the laboratory (Table 1, Quote 1A). Second and relatedly, some respondents identified knowledge gaps that contributed to epistemic uncertainty. These knowledge gaps related to the efficacy and hazards of GDTs in laboratory and cage experiments, population dynamics and sizes of natural populations in which GDTs may be used, and the roles of these populations in their ecosystems (Table 1, Quote 1B). Third, various respondents (all natural scientists) expressed concerns about the technical hurdles that have been encountered in making stable GDTs (Table 1, Quote 1C), in which the necessary components are expressed at the right time, place and level, without excessive fitness costs or resistance occurring. Similarly, some natural scientists reflected on the difficulty of getting GDTs to work in particular species. Finally, several respondents (all natural scientists) reflected on the complexities involved in translating results from the laboratory to the field; results in the laboratory may differ from results in ecosystems, complicating estimations about the effects of GDTs based on laboratory results (Table 1, Quote 1D).

Table 1 Quotations that illustrate theme 1

Dealing with epistemic uncertainty

Respondents had different views about the implications of the knowledge gaps and epistemic uncertainty related to GDTs and how this uncertainty should be dealt with. A few respondents (predominantly working within the social sciences and the NGO sector) argued the epistemic uncertainty related to GDTs provided a reason to support a moratorium on applications of GDTs outside the laboratory (Table 1, Quote 1E) (‘risks of intervention’ stance). Other respondents (working in various different disciplines) instead argued that such an approach would itself be harmful given the problematic status quo. According to them, the problems that GDTs aim to tackle are themselves attended by significant harms, and this should be factored into the decision on whether to use GDTs (‘risks of non-intervention’ stance). Rather than categorically refraining from applications of GDTs outside the laboratory, they argued more knowledge needs to be obtained about their (intended and unintended) effects through continued phased research to make an informed decision about whether field trials and more general releases should be allowed (Table 1, Quote 1F). Several respondents of the latter group argued that epistemic uncertainty is inherent to the initial stages of technology development and therefore does not provide an argument against developing and at some point testing these technologies (Quote 1G). One respondent, for instance, stressed that these knowledge gaps and related uncertainty do not provide a reason to put GDTs under intense scrutiny this early in the developmental process (Table 1, Quote 1H). One respondent argued a certain level of uncertainty could be justified for GDT applications that could be beneficial for human wellbeing (Table 1, Quote 1I).

Importance of setting realistic expectations

Although respondents thus varied in their assessment of how we should deal with the knowledge gaps and uncertainty related to GDTs, respondents with different views agreed that these knowledge gaps and uncertainties have not received enough attention in public and academic debates on GDTs. Various respondents mentioned that GDTs are regularly overhyped or presented as ‘silver bullets’. Respondents mentioned varying reasons why such overhyping is problematic and potentially harmful. On the one hand, several respondents (all natural scientists) who were in favor of developing GDTs mentioned that such overhyping could lead to unrealistic expectations about the technology, which could stifle further development if a first GDT release did not live up to expectations (Table 1, Quote 1I). On the other hand, several respondents with diverging views about GDTs (and from different disciplines) argued the silver bullet narrative created a false dichotomy in the debate about GDTs, in which employment of a perfectly functioning technology or acceptance of the status quo are presented as the only potential choices and outcomes, whereas the potential choices and outcomes are much more complex and uncertain (Table 1, Quote 1J).

In sum, respondents with different views on GDTs agreed there is epistemic uncertainty related to GDTs and identified similar knowledge gaps that ought to be addressed. Similarly, they agreed—albeit for different reasons—that realistic expectations should be set in the academic and public debates on GDTs: experts that participate in these debates should openly address the uncertainties and complexities involved in estimating the effects of GDTs. What they did not agree about was whether epistemic uncertainty provides a reason to refrain from testing GDTs outside the laboratory (‘risks of intervention’ stance) or rather—given the harms of the status quo—a reason to support phased research (‘risks of non-intervention’ stance). Respondents working in the natural sciences, philosophy/ethics and policy making somewhat more often held the former stance, whereas respondents working in the social sciences and NGO sector more often held the latter stance.

Theme 2: identifying and weighing alternatives

Although almost all respondents morally evaluated GDTs by comparing them to alternatives, respondents identified and used different alternatives in their comparisons, resulting in different conclusions about the permissibility of GDT applications. These alternatives can broadly be grouped in two categories: ‘downstream’ solutions that comprise conventional strategies to target vector-borne diseases, invasive species and agricultural pests, and ‘upstream’ solutions to these issues that instead comprise systematic changes to global health care, political and agricultural systems.

‘Downstream’ solutions: comparing GDTs to conventional strategies

Many respondents (from different disciplines) compared GDTs with conventional strategies used to target vector-borne diseases, invasive species and agricultural pests. For applications to target vector-borne diseases, these alternatives included strategies such as insecticides, impregnated bed nets, swamp draining and antimalarial medication; for applications to target invasive species, these alternatives included the use of pesticides, poisoning and ecosystem interventions such as introducing predators. Many respondents argued GDTs should be developed and/or used for particular applications if they provide benefits in comparison to conventional strategies that are currently being used. For example, numerous respondents contended that alternative conventional strategies have thus far been inadequate and/or harmful for the environment, other species or humans. For them, the harmfulness (Table 2, Quote 2A) and inadequacy (Table 2, Quote 2B) of these conventional strategies underline the need for an alternative strategy to tackle these problems, and GDTs could be such a strategy that could be used next to conventional approaches (Table 2, Quote 2C).

Table 2 Quotations that illustrate theme 2

‘Upstream’ solutions: comparing GDTs to systematic changes

Some respondents (mostly working within the NGO sector and the social sciences) instead compared GDTs with large-scale changes in our global health care, political and agricultural systems. According to these respondents, these underlying systems produce the problems we are trying to tackle in the first place, and if we do not look for the solution of the problem at that level, we are merely controlling the symptoms rather than the underlying problems. One respondent, for instance, argued agricultural pests are present due to the way in which we have designed our agricultural system, and should correspondingly be addressed by changing this system rather than by developing GDTs (Table 2, Quote 2D). Similarly, another respondent contended that, rather than develop GDTs, we should target vector-borne diseases by improving living conditions and health care facilities in the areas where these diseases are endemic (Table 2, Quote 2E). Correspondingly, as GDTs do not get to the root of the problems they aim to solve, these respondents considered GDTs an undesirable intervention.

Exhausting alternatives and feasibility of alternatives

Respondents disagreed with each other about whether the alternatives identified by those with a different view were feasible, and about whether they had been sufficiently explored. On the one hand, some respondents that opposed GDTs and argued in favor of ‘upstream’ solutions also questioned whether the conventional ‘downstream’ strategies to deal with vector-borne diseases and invasive species have been exhausted (Table 2, Quote 2F). On the other hand, some respondents who were open to (applications of) GDTs and considered other ‘downstream’ approaches insufficient or harmful, argued that the systematic ‘upstream’ changes advocated by opponents of GDTs to solve the problems at hand may be desirable, but not feasible. According to these respondents, past efforts and future projections by organizations such as the WHO demonstrate that it is naïve to think that the social determinants of health could be increased to such an extent that malaria transmission could be stopped (Table 2, Quote 2G).

All in all, most respondents morally evaluated GDTs by comparing them to alternatives, yet respondents held very different views on which alternatives should be considered (un)feasible and (in)sufficiently explored, and likewise which aspects of the global health care, political and agricultural systems should reasonably be taken as a given or as changeable. These different views, which may be summarized as ‘downstream solutions’ and ‘upstream solutions’ stances, were based on both empirical convictions about past efforts and future projections, as well as on normative convictions about the permissibility of using technology to solve problems that are (in part) caused or exacerbated by social or political processes. Respondents working within the natural sciences, philosophy/ethics and policy making were somewhat more inclined to have a ‘downstream solutions’ stance, whereas respondents working in the social sciences more often referred to the importance of ‘upstream solutions’. These different stances underline a core feature of disagreement about the moral permissibility of using GDTs.

Theme 3: the role of humans in nature

Finally, respondents had diverging views on what they considered justifiable interventions in nature, and whether GDTs could be considered a justifiable intervention. In other words, respondents differed in their assessment of what the role of humans in nature should be, and whether it is morally permissible to intervene in wild ecosystems in this way.

Assessing the moral permissibility of interventions in nature

Several respondents (none of whom were scientists or policy makers) argued we should not intervene in nature by using GDTs (‘non-interference’ stance). According to these respondents, the natural state of affairs is something that ought to be protected, and that would be disrupted by the use of GDTs. By using GDTs, some of them argued, humans would take up the role of ‘designers’ of nature, and this would be morally impermissible (Table 3, Quote 3A). Several respondents stressed these concerns about the role that humans should have in nature do not just apply to the use of GDTs, but are rather a part of broader concerns about the negative impact of humans on earth. These respondents emphasized that the human relationship to nature is largely skewed towards changing nature, rather than living in balance with nature and trying to preserve the natural state of affairs, and that this is generally undesirable (Table 3, Quote 3B). A few respondents mentioned it could be considered specifically problematic if suppression drives were used to eradicate unwanted populations or species (Table 3, Quote 3C).

Table 3 Quotations that illustrate theme 3

Other respondents (from different disciplines) disagreed with this view on the role of humans in nature and did not have fundamental problems with interfering in nature (‘interference’ stance). Some of these respondents argued that we intervene in nature all the time, and generally appear to consider it morally permissible to do so. Rather than looking specifically at GDTs, some of these respondents argued we should look comparatively at other interventions in nature that we consider morally permissible. If we consider other drastic interventions in nature morally permissible, it would be inconsistent to object to GDTs on the grounds that these technologies would be used to intentionally change nature (Table 3, Quote 3D). Some of these respondents also criticized opponents’ views on another ground, namely that they have an overly optimistic view of the goodness of nature. According to these respondents, nature is characterized by suffering and pain (as is, for instance, illustrated by the suffering of many wild animals). In their view this suffering provides moral grounds to intervene in nature, rather than to preserve it as it is (Table 3, Quote 3E). Other respondents questioned whether something like a ‘natural’ state of affairs that can be preserved actually exists. These respondents contended we should not see the current distribution of organisms as the ‘natural’ state of affairs which ought to be protected from human influence, as nature has been influenced by humans for millennia (Table 3, Quote 3F). According to these respondents, these in their opinion incorrect views of nature (as either inherently good or untouched and pristine) lead to unjustified conclusions about the impermissibility of using GDTs in nature.

Balancing the value and interests of humans, non-human animals and the environment

The positions of respondents about the role humans should take in nature were also related to their opinions about the value and interests of humans, non-human organisms and the environment, and how these should be balanced in decision-making about whether (and if so, under what conditions) to use GDTs. Various respondents argued that human interests outweigh the interests of non-human animals and the environment (Table 3, Quote 3G). Other respondents questioned the way in which human interests always take precedence over the value and interests of non-human animals and entities, and argued the latter are insufficiently taken into account (Table 3, Quote 3H). Several other respondents argued that the interests of humans should not trump the interests of non-human animals and the environment, and that GDTs should thus not be used (Table 3, Quote 3I). Others instead argued that these considerations limited potentially justifiable applications of GDTs to those applications that would achieve great benefits for humans (such as public-health benefits) while minimally affecting non-human animals (Table 3, Quote 3J).

In summary, respondents held different views on what the role of humans in nature should be, whether or not there is a moral reason to preserve the ‘natural’ state of affairs, and how the value and interests of humans, non-human animals and the environment should be balanced. Views on these issues influenced their views on GDTs and contributed to different stances on whether applications of GDTs could be justified, and if so, under what conditions. On these grounds, some respondents considered it permissible to intervene in nature using GDTs (‘interference stance’), whereas others did not (‘non-interference stance’). Natural scientists and policy makers were more inclined to hold the former stance, whereas respondents working within philosophy/ethics, the social sciences or NGOs were somewhat more inclined towards the latter.

Discussion

As far as we know, this study is the first in-depth interview study in which the moral views of a broad range of GDT experts were investigated. Our analysis sheds light on the considerations that influence the moral views of experts about the permissibility of (applications of) GDTs. Three main themes were identified: (1) how the uncertainty related to GDTs should be approached; (2) the alternatives to which GDTs should be compared and how these alternatives should be weighed; and (3) the role humans should have in nature.

In what follows, we will reflect on the implications and relevance of our empirical study for the debate on GDTs, relate its findings to the broader literature, and identify areas for further research. First, we will reflect on those issues about which experts largely agreed. Subsequently, we will discuss the disagreements that the study identified and underline issues that demand further (normative) reflection. Finally, we will outline some limitations of our study and provide recommendations for future research.

Common ground

To start, this analysis points to issues about which experts with different moral views on GDTs were in accordance, even if their overall views on the moral permissibility of these technologies differed vastly. First, experts with different moral views identified similar concerns with regard to the existing knowledge gaps for particular gene drive designs and applications, technical hurdles that would need to be overcome, and areas of uncertainty related to translation of results obtained in the laboratory to effects in the wild. Those with fundamentally different views on GDTs thus nonetheless agree that knowledge gaps exist and that more knowledge about particular topics should be obtained.

Second, experts pointed out that it is important to set realistic expectations about the complexities and uncertainties involved in estimating the effects of GDTs, both in terms of the potential benefits and risks. The importance of openness and transparency about uncertainties about both potential benefits and harms have been recognized by various organizations and authors in the GDT field (e.g. [43,44,45]), yet the results of our study emphasize that GDT experts nonetheless continue to see overhyping of these technologies as a risk. This is a relevant finding since expectations about new and emerging technologies are ‘performative’: they do not merely constitute representations of potential future scenarios, but also contribute to shaping the future, for example by influencing agenda setting and resource mobilization [35, 46,47,48]. As discussions on hype underline, expectations about emerging technologies can also have concrete undesirable impacts. For GDTs, it has been noted that unrealistic expectations could lead to premature calls for their release [1]. Furthermore, hyping could distort publics’ and communities’ understanding and expectations of these technologies, and potentially lead to a loss of credibility or trust if expectations are not fulfilled [46, 48]. Additionally, unrealistic expectations may divert resources away from alternative strategies that may in fact be better suited to tackle a particular problem. This may be seen as especially problematic in view of concerns about path dependency, the idea that investment in one particular solution to a problem makes it harder to switch to another solution even if it turned out to be superior [12, 46].

For GDT experts, and in particular GDT scientists, it is thus important to balance enthusiasm—which is both understandable and necessary to build momentum and raise funds in any scientific endeavor [49]—with the concomitant responsibility to be open about complexities, uncertainties and knowledge gaps. Moreover, this confirms the importance of obtaining more information to address current knowledge gaps, realistically weighing different alternatives to achieve particular aims [9] and designing adequate evaluation and mitigation plans [1]. Furthermore, it could be valuable to make different visions about GDTs themselves a subject of analysis throughout the process of their development. As the literature on ‘sociotechnical imaginaries’ illustrates, these visions are strongly influenced by broader visions of desirable futures [50]. A critical analysis of these different visions enables a transparent discussion about the plausibility and desirability of the different underlying arguments, premises and imaginations in which they are grounded, and could thereby help provide orientation on GDTs [35, 51].

Sources of disagreement

For each of the three themes that were identified, there were also fundamental disagreements; whilst experts with different opinions agree on particular (empirical) issues, they disagree about what we should do in light of these issues. In what follows, the sources of these disagreement will be explored in more detail.

Disciplinary differences

In previous studies, it has been posited that professionals from different disciplines have different approaches that affect their views on emerging technologies. For example, Ndoh, Cummings and Kuzma [52] describe disciplinary culture as a factor in risk perception. In their study, natural scientists for instance had lower expectations of human and environmental hazards of a synthetic biology case study than social scientists. Amongst other things, these differences may be explained by disciplines’ different epistemological underpinnings and knowledge approaches, which each have their own preoccupations, strengths and weaknesses [53]. These different disciplinary approaches are also tied to different value-based positions [54].

In our study, respondents working in the natural sciences, philosophy/ethics and policy making were somewhat more inclined to have ‘liberal’ stances (that leaned towards deploying GDTs) in relation to the three themes that were identified, whereas respondents working in the social sciences and NGO sector were more inclined to have ‘conservative’ stances (that leaned towards refraining from deployment of GDTs outside the laboratory). Whilst our study was set up with the aim of studying the moral views of a wide range of GDT experts rather than studying the influence of disciplinary cultures on these views, these differences underline the relevance of interdisciplinary collaboration in the development of and decision-making about GDTs, for each discipline can contribute its own insights and perspectives. At the same time, there was also significant variation in stances within groups of respondents working in the same discipline, demonstrating that the differences in moral views could not be attributed or reduced to the respondents’ disciplinary cultures. In the following sections, we will therefore get to the heart of these disagreements by investigating the basis for the identified tensions in more detail.

Consequences of knowledge gaps and epistemic uncertainty

The first source of disagreement that was identified concerns the consequences of the knowledge gaps and epistemic uncertainty related to GDTs. Epistemic uncertainty is widely recognized as a persistent characteristic of new and emerging technologies in general and of GDTs in particular [1, 3, 10, 21, 45]. As has also been recognized, reducing epistemic uncertainty about the risks of GDTs could paradoxically require an environmental release that itself poses risksFootnote 3 [21, 25], underlining the importance of determining when knowledge gaps can be considered sufficiently resolved to make responsible decisions about specific GDT applications [25, 55].

In our study, some respondents argued the knowledge gaps and uncertainty provide a rationale to proceed with phased testing (potentially including, at some point, field testing) to obtain more data, whereas others argued there should be a moratorium on any application of GDTs outside the laboratory. Whilst both groups of respondents argued that it is important to prevent risks and harms, they operationalized this differently: the latter group contended greater precaution should be taken against the risks and harms associated with the use of GDTs (‘risks of intervention’ stance), whereas the former group instead placed greater weight on the opportunity costs associated with failing to use GDTs (‘risks of non-intervention’ stance) and argued proceeding with GDT deployment could be acceptable even if uncertainty remained.

The identified stances can also be recognized in broader disputes between those that respectively take a ‘precautionary’ or a ‘proactionary’ stance toward emerging technologies, in which the latter have argued that precaution in one respect often leads to increased risks and harms on other fronts [56,57,58]. A crucial point of difference between these different parties also relates to who should bear the burden of proof with regards to a technology’s potential to cause harm, with those that consider novel technologies ‘guilty until proven innocent’ versus ‘innocent until proven guilty’ at opposite sides of the spectrum [57]. At the same time, it has also been argued that it could be possible to escape this polarization by distributing the burden of proof [57], explicitly framing precautionary courses of action as precautionary “with respect to something” (p. 469) [56], and looking for a middle ground of ‘optimal’ rather than ‘maximum precaution’ [59]. Whilst these proposals may not resolve the dispute between those with different stances, they may nonetheless help to bring points of disagreement more squarely into focus in related discussions. Moreover, these different stances invoke discussion about other related questions such as what constitutes a ‘benefit’ or a ‘risk’ in the first place [45, 60], and how potential benefits and risks should be weighed.

Weighing of alternative strategies

The second source of disagreement that was identified in this study concerns the weighing of alternative strategies to confront vector-borne diseases, invasive species and agricultural pests. Whereas many respondents compared GDTs to other ‘downstream’ solutions such as pesticides, other respondents argued ‘upstream’ solutions that tackle these problems at their root should be deployed instead. Some respondents, for instance, stressed that the impact of vector-borne diseases such as malaria is also determined by social and political factors, and argued that deploying GDTs would thus not offer lasting solutions. These different stances were also mentioned in the report of a workshop that identified governance issues and research needs in relation to GDTs [25].

To some degree, these different stances may be attributable to a different understanding of the empirical data on the efficacy of past efforts to confront these problems and the factors that influence future projections of success if these strategies are continued or intensified [12]. To the extent this is the case, making empirical convictions about both ‘downstream’ and ‘upstream’ alternatives to GDTs will further (policy) discussions about GDTs. However, these different stances also point to deeper normative questions about the (im)permissibility of ‘technological fixes’, a recurrent theme in debates about biotechnology [61] that has also received some attention in the debate on GDTs [12, 45, 62]. Such techno-fixes have, amongst others, been critiqued on the ground that they reduce a social problem to a technical problem, which could both perpetuate the underlying problem [1, 62] and result in problematic side-effects [45]. Moreover, it has been argued that techno-fixes are based on mistaken convictions about the inherent progressiveness of science and technologies [61]. At the same time, it has been noted that the comparatively quick and targeted nature of GDTs could nonetheless make them an attractive solution [1], raising relevant questions about whether we ought to take ‘ideal theory’ or ‘non-ideal theory’ (which focuses on what we ought to do in non-ideal circumstances) as a starting point for ethical decision making about GDTs.

Intervening in nature

A third normative dispute related to the permissibility of using GDTs to intervene in nature for our aims and benefit. Experts’ views of nature and the role of humans in it, as well as their views on the value and interests of humans, non-human animals and the environment, impacted their moral view on intervening in nature with (particular applications of) GDTs. Views of nature and what is ‘natural’ have been found to influence views on a broad range of emerging technologies [63, 64] and have long since led to debate about the ideal of nature and the (ir)relevance of naturalness as an ethical criterion [9, 65, 66]. As has also been pointed out, people across the world moreover tend to have different views of (the role of humans) nature [45], underlining that it would be highly relevant to study how related perspectives affect non-Western experts’ and publics’ moral views of GDTs.

In the literature about GDTs, various authors and organizations have indeed pointed out that perspectives on the relationship of humans to nature play an important role in the debate about these technologies [1, 30, 45, 67, 68]. Relevant points of contention in this debate include if and on what grounds human independence is valuable in (wild) species and ecosystems [45, 62], if and on what grounds GDTs differ in morally relevant ways from other interactions with non-human nature [45, 67] and if and on what grounds it is permissible to genetically modify non-human organisms to achieve conservation goals rather than changing human behavior to achieve these goalsFootnote 4 [62]. As the results of our study imply, stances about the permissibility of intervening in nature in this way also hinge on convictions about the value or moral status of different organisms, what duties we have towards these different entities, and how duties towards different entities should be prioritized in case they conflict. Although these featured less prominently in respondents’ statements, convictions about the value or moral status of holistic entities such as species [13] and ecosystems are likely to be of similar relevance.

For all these different normative disputes, critical analysis and explicit discussion can help to disentangle the complexity of the problems at hand, challenge potentially unwarranted assumptions and enable individuals to develop well-considered judgements on these issues. GDT experts, which actively shape these technologies and the debate about them, may take the stances and considerations outlined in this paper as a starting point for further reflection on their (implicit) views on these matters and how these affect their views on GDTs. At the same time, it is important to realize that genuine value pluralism about many of these issues will remain [69], underlining the need for fair governance and decision-making procedures. Amongst others, important procedural ethical questions relate to who should make decisions, how these decisions should be taken, and when deliberation should be concluded [1, 15,16,17].

Limitations and recommendations for future research

Our results should be interpreted in the context of the following limitations. First, the scope of our study was relatively broad. As it was the first large and in-depth interview study on experts’ moral views regarding GDTs, we chose to conduct an exploratory study to allow experts to bring up issues they considered relevant. Although saturation was reached on the codes and themes identified, further research should explore these topics in more depth. Second, any qualitative interview study is prone to interviewer and researcher bias; a different interviewer could have focused their attention on different aspects of the respondents’ answers, and grouped the codes and themes differently. Third, our study represents a subgroup of GDT experts which prominently contributed to the academic and/or policy debates on GDTs. While these experts offered a diverse range of perspectives, they were predominantly employed in the global North. It would be highly relevant to conduct additional qualitative interview studies with experts in other countries to investigate whether there are cultural or otherwise region-dependent differences amongst experts. In particular, it would be relevant to focus on respondents from countries where GDTs may be used to combat vector-borne diseases and/or invasive species, such as Burkina Faso, Ghana, India, Australia and/or New Zealand. Similarly, it would be very relevant to conduct a qualitative study amongst the communities living in areas where GDTs may be deployed. Finally, many of the issues identified in this study warrant a more detailed normative analysis.

Conclusion

GDTs are developing rapidly and have been proposed as a potential strategy to address several major problems, but have also raised a range of ethical questions. These technologies themselves, the academic debate on the associated ethical questions, and the related policymaking are shaped by experts from different disciplines. This interview study helps to disentangle the polarized debate on GDTs by providing a better understanding of the moral views of GDT experts and elucidating where they agree and disagree. The obtained insights provide valuable stepping-stones for a constructive debate about underlying value conflicts and point to topics that deserve further academic scrutiny. Further evaluation of these and other morally relevant aspects of GDTs should take place in co-production with diverse stakeholders in parallel to the technological development of GDTs. In this way, these considerations can inform the design and implementation of these technologies and facilitate their responsible development.

Availability of data and materials

The interview guide is available in the supplementary information. The datasets generated and analyzed during the current study are not publicly available because individual privacy could be compromised; since the gene drive field is relatively small, individual participants could reasonably be identifiable if the full datasets were provided. The individual privacy of the participants is considered of particular importance because the data in question include participants’ political opinions and philosophical beliefs, which are deemed sensitive and get specific protection under the General Data Protection Regulation (GDPR; article 9).

Notes

  1. If organisms have an inheritance pattern that can be biased, typically meaning that they can reproduce sexually (70).

  2. We will report on the findings related to the procedural ethical aspects of GDTs, i.e. the questions, concerns, and implications that relate to the process of governance of and decision-making about GDTs, in a separate manuscript.

  3. As has been recognized by GDT experts in a workshop on gene drive governance and research needs, the use of localized rather than self-sustained GDTs could reduce this complexity (25).

  4. In this sense, the third theme is interrelated with the discussion on techno-fixes, which calls the permissibility of doing so into question. Indeed, techno-fixes have also been critiqued on the ground that they derive from a commitment to an anthropocentric conception of the human relationship to the (rest of) nature (59).

Abbreviations

COREQ:

COnsolidated criteria for REporting Qualitative studies

CRISPR/Cas9:

Clustered Regularly Interspaced Palindromic Repeats/CRISPR-associated protein 9

GDTs:

Gene drive technologies

NGO:

Non-governmental organization

References

  1. The National Academies of Sciences Engineering & Medicine (NASEM). Gene drives on the horizon: advancing science, navigating uncertainty, and aligning research with public values. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press; 2016.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Oye KA, Esvelt K, Appleton E, Catteruccia F, Church G, Kuiken T, et al. Regulating gene drives. Science. 2014;345(61):626–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Royal Society. Gene drive research—why it matters. 2018. https://royalsociety.org/~/media/policy/Publications/2018/08-11-18-gene-drive-statement.pdf.

  4. Champer J, Buchman A, Akbari OS. Cheating evolution: engineering gene drives to manipulate the fate of wild populations. Nat Rev Genet. 2016;17(3):146–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Alphey L. Can CRISPR-Cas9 gene drives curb malaria? Nat Biotechnol. 2016;34(2):149–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Esvelt KM, Smidler AL, Catteruccia F, Church GM. Concerning RNA-guided gene drives for the alteration of wild populations. Elife. 2014;3(e03401):1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Neve P. Gene drive systems: do they have a place in agricultural weed management? Pest Manag Sci. 2018;74(12):2671–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Grunwald HA, Gantz VM, Poplawski G, Xu XRS, Bier E, Cooper KL. Super-Mendelian inheritance mediated by CRISPR–Cas9 in the female mouse germline. Nature. 2019;566(7742):105–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. De Graeff N, Jongsma KR, Johnston J, Hartley S, Bredenoord AL. The ethics of genome editing in non-human animals: a systematic review of reasons reported in the academic literature. Philos Trans R Soc B Biol Sci. 2019;374(1772):20180106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Lunshof JE, Birnbaum A. Adaptive risk management of gene drive experiments: biosafety, biosecurity, and ethics. Appl Biosaf J ABSA Int. 2017;22(3):97–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Thompson PB. The roles of ethics in gene drive research and governance. J Responsib Innov. 2018;5:S159–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Callies DE. The ethical landscape of gene drive research. Bioethics. 2019;348:1091–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Pugh J. Driven to extinction? The ethics of eradicating mosquitoes with gene-drive technologies. J Med Ethics. 2016;42(9):578–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Kuzma J, Rawls L. Engineering the wild: gene drives and intergenerational equity. Jurimetr J Law Sci Technol. 2016;56(3):279.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Resnik DB. Ethics of community engagement in field trials of genetically modified mosquitoes. Dev World Bioeth. 2018;18(2):135–43. https://doi.org/10.1111/dewb.12147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Neuhaus CP. Community engagement and field trials of genetically modified insects and animals. Hastings Cent Rep. 2018;48(1):25–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Kolopack PA, Lavery JV. Informed consent in field trials of gene-drive mosquitoes. Gates Open Res. 2017;1:1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. The African Union, The New Partnership for Africa’s Development. Gene drives for malaria control and elimination in Africa. 2017.

  19. Westra J, van der Vlugt CJB, Roesink CH, Hogervorst PAM, Glandorf DCM. Gene drives policy report. RIVM letter report 2016-0023. p. 1–31. https://www.rivm.nl/dsresource?objectid=46b949bd-f34f-4206-8859-2b01d1db4dae&type=org&disposition=inline.

  20. Australian Academy of Science. Synthetic gene drives in Austrialia: Implications of emerging technologies. Canberra: Australian Academy of Science; 2017.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Redford KH, Brooks TM, Nicholas BW, Adams JS. Genetic frontiers for conservation: an assessment of synthetic biology and biodiversity conservation: technical assessment. Genetic frontiers for conservation: an assessment of synthetic biology and biodiversity conservation: technical assessment. 2019.

  22. Roberts A, De Andrade PP, Okumu F, Quemada H, Savadogo M, Singh JA, et al. Results from the workshop “problem formulation for the use of gene drive in mosquitoes.” Am J Trop Med Hyg. 2017;96(3):530–3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Giese B, Frieß JL, Barton NH, Messer PW, Débarre F, Schetelig MF, et al. Gene drives: dynamics and regulatory matters—a report from the workshop “ evaluation of spatial and temporal control of gene drives,” April 4–5 , 2019, Vienna 2019;1900151:1–3.

  24. Carter SR, Friedman RM. Policy and regulatory issues for gene drives in insects, workshop report. 2016. p. 1–21.

  25. Kuzma J, Gould F, Brown Z, Collins J, Delborne J, Frow E, et al. A roadmap for gene drives: using institutional analysis and development to frame research needs and governance in a systems context. J Responsib Innov. 2018;5:S13-39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. James et al. Pathway to deployment of gene drive mosquitoes as a potential 1001 biocontrol tool for elimination of malaria in sub-Saharan Africa: recommendations of a scientific working group. Am J Trop Med Hyg. 2018;98(6):1–49.

  27. Long et al. Core commitments for field trials of gene drive organisms. Biotechnol Gov. 370(6523):1417–19.

  28. James S, Collins FH, Welkhoff PA, Emerson C, Godfray JHC, Gottlieb M, et al. Pathway to deployment of gene drive mosquitoes as a potential biocontrol tool for elimination of malaria in sub-Saharan Africa: recommendations of a scientific working group. Am J Trop Med Hyg. 2018;98(6):1–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. SynBioWatch. A call for conservation with a conscience: no place for gene drives in conservation. 2016. http://www.synbiowatch.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/09/letter_vs_genedrives.pdf.

  30. Civil Society Working Group on Gene Drives. Reckless driving: gene drives and the end of nature. 2016. https://seedfreedom.info/wp-content/uploads/2016/08/ETC_genedrivers_v7_4web.pdf.

  31. African Center for Biodiversity. Critique of African Union and NEPAD’s positions on gene drive mosquitoes for Malaria elimination. Melville: African Center for Biodiversity; 2018.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Braverman I. Gene drives, nature, governance: an ethnographic perspective. In: Braverman I, editor. Gene editing, law, and the environment—life beyond the human. New York, NY: Routledge; 2018. p. 55–74.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Civil Society Working Group on Gene Drives. The case for a global moratorium on genetically-engineered gene drives. 2016. http://www.etcgroup.org/sites/www.etcgroup.org/files/files/cbd_cop_13_gene_drive_moratorium_briefing.pdf.

  34. Rehmann-Sutter C, Porz R, Scully JL. How to relate the empirical to the normative. Camb Q Healthc Ethics. 2012;21(4):436–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Grunwald A. Converging technologies: visions, increased contingencies of the conditio humana, and search for orientation. Futures. 2007;39(4):380–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Sand M. Futures, visions, and responsibility. An ethics of innovation. Wiesbaden: Springer; 2018.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  37. Tong A, Sainsbury P, Craig J. Consolidated criteria for reporting qualitative research (COREQ): a 32-item checklist for interviews and focus groups. Int J Qual Heal Care. 2007;19(6):349–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Creswell JW. Qualitative inquiry & research design: choosing among five approaches. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE Publications; 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Hennink MM, Kaiser BN, Marconi VC. Code saturation versus meaning saturation: how many interviews are enough? Qual Health Res. 2017;27(4):591–608.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Sollie P. On uncertainty in ethics and technology. In: Sollie P, Düwell M, editors. Evaluating new technologies—methodological problems for the ethical assessment of technology developments. Berlin: Springer; 2009. p. 141–58. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-2229-5.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  41. Braun V, Clarke V. Using thematic analysis in psychology. Qual Res Psychol. 2006;2006(3):77–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Kvale S. InterViews: an introduction to qualitative research interviewing. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, Inc; 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Emerson C, James S, Littler K, Randazzo F. Principles for gene drive research. Science. 2017;358(6367):1135–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Min J, Smidler AL, Najjar D, Esvelt KM. Harnessing gene drive. J Responsib Innov. 2018;5:S40-65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Critical Scientists Switzerland (CSS), European Network of Scientists for Social and Environmental Responsibility (ENSSER), Vereinigung Deutscher Wissenschaftler (VDW). Gene drives. A report on their science, applications, social aspects, ethics and regulations. Bern: Critical Scientists Switzerland (CSS), European Network of Scientists for Social and Environmental Responsibility (ENSSER) & Vereinigung Deutscher Wissenschaftler (VDW); 2019.

  46. Borup M, Brown N, Konrad K, Van Lente H. The sociology of expectations in science and technology. Technol Anal Strateg Manag. 2006;18(3):489–93.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Van Lente H. Promising technology. The dynamics of expectations in technological developments. Delft: Eburon; 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Dignum M. The power of large technological visions: the promise of hydrogen energy (1970–2010). Eindhoven: Technische Universiteit Eindhoven; 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Caulfield T. Spinning the genome: why science hype matters. Perspect Biol Med. 2018;61(4):560–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Jasanoff S, Kim S-H, editors. dreamscapes of modernity: sociotechnical imaginaries. Chicago: Johns Hopkins University Press; 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Grunwald A. Modes of orientation provided by futures studies: making sense of diversity and divergence. Eur J Futur Res. 2014;2(1):30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Ndoh C, Cummings CL, Kuzma J. The role of expert disciplinary cultures in assessing risks and benefits of synthetic biology. In: Trump BD, Cummings CL, Kuzma J, Linkov I, editors. Synthetic biology 2020: frontiers in risk analysis and governance. Cham: Springer; 2020.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Althaus CE. A disciplinary perspective on the epistemological status of risk. Risk Anal. 2005;25(3):567–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Sarewitz D. How science makes environmental controversies worse. Environ Sci Policy. 2004;7(5):385–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Munthe C. Precaution and ethics: handling risks, uncertainties and knowledge gaps in the regulation of new biotechnologies. 2017. www.bundespublikationen.admin.ch.

  56. Sandin P. The precautionary principle and the concept of precaution. Environ Values. 2004;13(4):461–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. Van Den Belt H, Gremmen B. Between precautionary principle and “sound science”: distributing the burdens of proof. J Agric Environ Ethics. 2002;15(1):103–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. Kaebnick GE, Gusmano MK, Murray TH. The ethics of synthetic biology: next steps and prior questions. Hast Cent Rep. 2014;44(6):S4-26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. Wiener JBW. Precaution in a multirisk world. In: Paustenbach DJ, editor. Human and ecological risk assessment: theory and practice. New York, NY: Wiley; 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Calvert J. Governing in the context of uncertainty. Hastings Cent Rep. 2014;44(6):S31–3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  61. Scott D. The technological fix criticisms of agricultural biotechnology. 2005. p. 1–20.

  62. Sandler R. The ethics of genetic engineering and gene drives in conservation. Conserv Biol. 2019;34(2):1–8.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Macnaghten P, Davies SR, Kearnes M. Understanding public responses to emerging technologies: a narrative approach. J Environ Policy Plan. 2015. https://doi.org/10.1080/1523908X.2015.1053110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  64. Shaw A. “It just goes against the grain.” Public understandings of genetically modified (GM) food in the UK. Public Underst Sci. 2002;11(3):273–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  65. Siipi H. Dimensions of naturalness. Ethics Environ. 2008;13(1):71–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  66. Kaebnick GE. Humans in nature: the world as we find it and the world as we create it. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Sustainability Council of New Zealand. A Constitutional Moment. Gene drives and international Governance. 2018.

  68. Braverman I. Gene drives, nature, governance: an ethnographic perspective. 2017.

  69. Bovenkerk B. The biotechnology debate, vol. 29. Dordrecht: Springer; 2012. p. 19–61. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2691-8.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  70. Alphey LS, Crisanti A, Randazzo F, Akbari OS. Standardizing the definition of gene drive. PNAS. 2020;117(49):30864–7. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2020417117/-/DCSupplemental.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are grateful to all participants for their contribution to this study.

Funding

This project was supported by the division of Applied and Engineering Sciences of The Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO; project no. 15804). The funding body was not involved in any aspects related to the study.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

NG, KRJ and ALB were responsible for the concept and design of the study. NG was responsible for the recruitment of interview participants, data collection and initial drafting of the article. NG conducted the thematic analysis, to which KRJ and ALB provided substantial input along the way. KRJ and ALB critically revised the manuscript. All authors approved the final version of the article.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to N. de Graeff.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate

Participants were informed about the study and agreed to participate via e-mail. Prior to the start of the interview, participants were verbally informed about the interview study, its recording and the pseudonimized analysis of interview data. Each participant gave verbal consent to the interview, which was audiotaped. The research protocol including the procedure for verbal consent was submitted to the research ethics committee of the University Medical Center Utrecht for review prior to the initiation of research. The research ethics committee determined that this study was exempt from the Medical Research Involving Humans Act (research proposal no. 18/618). Written consent was not considered legally or ethically necessary for this study because the research was deemed to involve minimal risk and the set-up includes sufficient guarantees that the respondents voluntarily participate in the research.

Consent for publication

Not applicable.

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Supplementary Information

Additional file 1

. Interview guide.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated in a credit line to the data.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

de Graeff, N., Jongsma, K.R. & Bredenoord, A.L. Experts’ moral views on gene drive technologies: a qualitative interview study. BMC Med Ethics 22, 25 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-021-00588-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-021-00588-5

Keywords