Skip to main content

Extremely premature birth bioethical decision-making supported by dialogics and pragmatism

Abstract

Moral values in healthcare range widely between interest groups and are principally subjective. Disagreements diminish dialogue and marginalize alternative viewpoints. Extremely premature births exemplify how discord becomes unproductive when conflicts of interest, cultural misunderstanding, constrained evidence review, and peculiar hierarchy compete without the balance of objective standards of reason. Accepting uncertainty, distributing risk fairly, and humbly acknowledging therapeutic limits are honorable traits, not relativism, and especially crucial in our world of constrained resources. We think dialogics engender a mutual understanding that: i) transitions beliefs beyond bias, ii) moves conflict toward pragmatism (i.e., the truth of any position is verified by subsequent experience), and iii) recognizes value pluralism (i.e., human values are irreducibly diverse, conflicting, and ultimately incommensurable). This article provides a clear and useful Point-Counterpoint of extreme prematurity controversies, an objective neurodevelopmental outcomes table, and a dialogics exemplar to cultivate shared empathetic comprehension, not to create sides from which to choose. It is our goal to bridge the understanding gap within and between physicians and bioethicists. Dialogics accept competing relational interests as human nature, recognizing that ultimate solutions satisfactory to all are illusory, because every choice has downside. Nurturing a collective consciousness via dialogics and pragmatism is congenial to integrating objective evidence review and subjective moral-cultural sentiments, and is that rarest of ethical constructs, a means and an end.

Peer Review reports

Background

Accurately summarizing health outcomes and bioethical complexities related to extremely premature birth is challenging, perhaps unrealistic. The periviability literature is multiforme, lending itself to arbitrary selection of data and opinions of personal or institutional congruence, rather than broad consensus. Divergent cultural and religious beliefs, conflicts of interest, financial priorities, resource utilization, and the socio-economic struggles of families deserve far more scrutiny, yet persistently avoid analysis. Because of these peculiarities we submit an alternative model based upon the principles of dialogics and pragmatism. Our goal is to bridge the collective understanding gap within and between physicians and bioethicists.

Passionate ideology regarding palliative care versus neonatal intensive care for extremely premature infants hugely impacts health and social outcomes, but is curiously far less examined than medical interventions and therapies. Family preferences viewed as acceptable or not, sophisticated technologic therapies seen as experimental or not, and whether cultural heterogeneity is reducible to common moral foundations or not, are all issues beholden to disparate emotions and beliefs [1,2,3,4].

Physicians acknowledge uncertainty yet are risk averse. Arbitrary lines-of-demarcation that deny the ambiguous characteristics of nearly every feature of extremely premature birth tend to serve the interests of those with power. Sorites Paradox should be a feature of bioethical philosophy. When sharp demarcations cannot be established with assurance—“This is clearly X and that is certainly Y” – we are well-advised to minimize inflexible positions of “X is right” and “Y is wrong” [5,6,7,8].

Statements regarding what is moral imply what is not moral—the tautology that generates discord. The problem is that extreme prematurity disputes are scarcely ethical exercises of “We agree to disagree” because binary medical decisions are required in emergency scenarios. Without the luxury of time, key judgments must be made regarding fetal monitoring, antenatal corticosteroids, cesarean section, intubation, or not. Impending birth makes some decision paths convenient in the short-term for select participants, but later regretted and costly, depending upon subsequent events. We believe this dissensus is a fundamental of extreme prematurity, but not necessarily to be avoided nor solved, rather acknowledged and incorporated interactively along with features of consensus [9,10,11,12,13].

Because every choice has potential downside, extremely premature birth is a paradigm of human suffering and tragedy. There is no uniform pathway for anyone that eliminates risk, pain, and guarantees well-being. The decision-making process and family reactions to clinical events ebb and flow with changing notions of “right” and “wrong”. Physicians should avoid framing extreme prematurity and periviability choices as an opportunity for pregnant women and families (and least of all physicians) to be noble or heroic [14, 15].

Our goals: i) capsulize recent extremely premature infant long-term neurodevelopmental outcome reports to bolster objective shared decision-making (Additional file 1: Table S1), ii) provide a practical Point-Counterpoint of divergent viewpoints related to extreme prematurity (Table 1), and iii) illustrate the productive nature of dialogics and pragmatism as the methodologies that encourage listening and information exchange, and the relational interactions that nurture a collective consciousness which enhance empathetic understanding and bioethical decision making. Readers are encouraged to reflect upon this manuscript because understanding the nature of dialogics and pragmatism will encourage their important contributions to our understanding of extreme prematurity.

Table 1 Point—Counterpoint dialogic summary of the principal viewpoints and issues of extremely premature birth—Neonatal Intensive Care versus Palliative Care

Dialectics (thesis-antithesis-synthesis) assume there is inherent, constant progress toward some inexorable goal or hallowed truth, and are especially seductive in healthcare where absolutism, technology, and scientism are dominant motifs. Absolutism requires participants acquiesce to the cultural, religious, or political beliefs of others in power, and scientism is believing the scientific method and technology are the ultimate paradigms for solving human problems [16,17,18]. In sharp contrast, dialogics highlight that ultimate, ordained solutions to complex ethical issues have never in human history been entirely rational, objective, much less satisfactory to all [19,20,21].

Dialogics are consummately suitable to extremely premature births because this communication philosophy recognizes that language and information exchange affect us in multiple directions that resist convenient synopsis. We modify words and data (and vice versa) as continual interactions and flux, each of us biased, culture-influenced, yet not necessarily fixed in sentiment or position [18,19,20, 22, 23].

Moral intuitions are neither fixed deontological maxims nor calculable utilitarian equations, but rather rooted in biologic, social, and ideologic underpinnings that are products of human evolution [24]. These intuitions, if part of reflective dialogic equilibrium, become part of our collective consciousness [25]. The present affects our evaluation of the past no less than the reverse. Each person’s beliefs and authority in evolving dialogics hold more, or less, salience and authenticity depending upon the circumstance and precise issue, and not as hierarchy, but as interactive network dynamics [26].

Dialogics shun absolutism, and incorporate value pluralism rather than relativism, a crucial distinction. Value pluralism: History consistently illustrates that core human values conflict, are often incommensurable with no common currency, may or may not be rational, and are inherently irresolvable absent of hierarchy and power differentials. In contrast, moral relativism: You think two situations or judgments are morally different, but you are mistaken, they are morally equivalent [16, 17, 27]. Dialogics bolster pragmatism, i.e., the useful truth of any belief or policy is steadily borne out by the sum of all subsequent events. Pragmatism is empiric validity, not compromise; it is instrumental to fact-finding, not mere opinions devoid of objectivity and principle [28].

Main text (dialogic discussion)

Author A: Anxiety can spring from denial of self-responsibility. Our lives possess accountable freedom to create authenticity without suppliance to external authority or supernaturalism. Within extreme prematurity conflicts we disguise angst by drifting to unrestrained interventionism and technology (scientism). When we avoid the self-responsibility of deciding collaboratively what is truly meaningful as a community in the here-and-now, then we perpetuate healthcare dysfunction, even nihilism [29].

Author B: Decisions for extremely premature infants are life-altering, families should not be denied the opportunity of self-responsibility for decision-making [30]. Nor should appeal to external authority or supernaturalism be rebuffed. Supernaturalism provides a foundation for some families, allowing them to cope with the uncertainty of life-and-death decisions [31]. Denying religious values could drive nihilism. Yet supernaturalism—or any belief system—can result in care requests many physicians consider morally wrong.

Author A: Physicians confuse compassion and pity. Compassion is sympathetic concern for others’ suffering and is innate to human nature. Pity enhances oneself by reducing others to neediness. We create meaning by being powerful enough to help. Pity falsely stages us as better than others, this perpetuates dependence and vulnerability [32, 33].

Author B: Rather than differentiating compassion and pity, we should emphasize to pregnant women and families “I imagine you would prefer to not be in this difficult position, but you are, and I am here to inform and support you.” This does not imply “It is difficult for you to decide what to do, so let me decide.” Communicating with compassion the truth of unbiased, hopeful, frightening information regarding risks and benefits of care options is essential to informed consent [34].

Author A: Social media influencers often imply honesty is the principal issue of conflict. But it is not honesty that is the modern arbiter of disputes, it has become sincerity. Sincerity is conflated with honesty. If I hold a sentiment deeply for my special reasons, it becomes inviolable. This has become preferable to dialogics and pragmatism; it is me claiming my rights. In periviability controversies, physicians convey sincerity as part of their authority; we can be sincere but not honest, a substitute for integrity [35].

Author B: Fundamental to periviability dialogics is tolerance. Replies to value-laden questions, e.g. “What would you do doctor?”, are acceptable assuming declaration of physician values and biases accompany the reply [36]. A sincere answer that involves non-disclosure of evidence-based information inherent to authentic dialogics is regrettable. Examples of intolerable physician answers might be “There is unfortunately nothing we can do at 22 weeks” or “Babies born at 25 weeks do well, so intensive care is best.” Physicians should acknowledge the way evidence is presented can be either positive (“survival”, “free of neurodevelopmental impairment”), or negative (“death”, “neurodevelopmental impairment”), or honest (providing both the positive and negative framing of evidence) (Additional file 1: Table S1).

Author A: We respectfully accept pregnant women discussing their religious values. But physicians should not assume pregnant women nor colleagues desire to know practitioners’ religious beliefs, much less agree with them. Inserting religious or political doctrine is particularly egregious with pregnant women because of their vulnerability. They deserve sympathetic understanding and medical expertise, not personal bias and absolutism. Deeply religious individuals of various faiths choose palliative care in similar scenarios that other equally devout people choose intensive care. Physicians may have difficulty integrating this characteristic of value pluralism [24, 37].

Author B: Most people have a worldview that guides decision-making. A physician’s dialogic and pragmatic role is not primarily to make the decision, but to clarify, guide, and support compassionate, reasoned pathways. If physicians are clear regarding their function, then beliefs that they legitimately possess should have minimal effect on the pregnant woman’s decision [38, 39]. Physicians should understand that whether particular neurodevelopmental impairment(s) are “significant” in the real world varies among institutions, countries, and between practitioners and families based on qualitative judgements. There are no precise, universal normative categories regarding the quality of life or value of children.

Author A: Ambiguity encourages wishful thinking, which leads to “right” and “wrong” declarations. This devolves to “I think this is good, you should too.” Physicians create tragedy because lines-of-demarcation in ethical controversies are seldom logically defined nor clinically absolute (Sorites Paradox). Lines-of-demarcation declared definitive often originate from hierarchy and power-differentials [27, 40, 41].

Author B: Practicality necessitates certain lines-of-demarcation. A simple analogy is the selection of voting age in democracies. If it is age 18 years, then some individuals 17 years + 364 days could surely make an educated choice but are not allowed, simply to facilitate clear, implementable voting processes. When there is a spectrum of moral opinions within a group of healthcare providers, choosing a line-of-demarcation can allow a coherent, implementable team approach. The choice of such a line should not be permanent. The bioethical culture of healthcare should adapt when sociological, epistemological, or medical findings necessitate change [42].

Author A: Physicians advocate evidence-based medicine in general, yet inconsistently in periviability decisions. Standardized, informed consent is arbitrarily applied, e.g., recommended for surgery but not broader life support interventions [43, 44]. Extreme prematurity is laden with uncertainty, risk, and experimental therapies. Neonatologists should not assume specialized knowledge of medical conditions legitimizes their moral authority. Evidence based practices and compassion are family-centered bedrocks that begin before decisions regarding extremely premature birth are made, not after admission to the NICU [11, 12].

Author B: Sound arguments support the importance of structured, informed consent. The disclosure of relevant knowledge is foundational to the consent process. Understanding information enhances the autonomy of a family. We accept pregnant women as surrogate decision-makers and support them by appropriate disclosure of information [45]. The volume and technical content can overwhelm decision-making capacity. Studies of decision support tools suggest parents think the amount of information as enough, and if anything, be increased. Under-informing pregnant women is a greater impediment to informed consent than over-informing [46, 47].

Author A: Survival rates are increasing but neurodevelopmental impairment rates, particularly < 25 weeks gestation, are not improving [48]. In fact, outcomes may be worsening over time when broader neuropsychiatric conditions are included (Additional file 1: Table S1). Quality of life is rated lower in surviving extremely premature infants as they become teen-agers and adults [49,50,51,52]. Advocates of universal intensive care conflate improving survival and not-improving long-term health. This enables their authority of ever-expanding intervention, despite publishing no evidence of improving comprehensive neurodevelopmental outcomes [53, 54]. Claims of conscience are valid bidirectionally: “I choose not to participate in palliative care” and “I choose not to participate in intensive care” are both legitimate. Physicians who support palliative care options no more find “favor” with an infant death than a physicist finds “favor” with gravity [55, 56].

Author B: Fear of death is a universal apprehension; for physicians this includes the fear of causing death. Given the inevitable result of palliative care, we may possess a heuristic that predisposes toward advocating intensive care. Introspection about death and the moral status of the fetus/newborn challenges us to study broader empirical experiences of women and families of diverse culture and circumstance who have lived all the different care choices, and thus understand multiforme long-term outcomes [57, 58]. Gaining more empirical data about how physicians may experience fear in terms of “causing death” or “creating children with neurodevelopmental problems” would advance our understanding of physician normative views.

Author A: Certain population healthcare objectives are unambiguous—providers receive ‘X’ dollars to care for ‘Y’ patients per annum. This requires priority-setting, inexorable difficult choices, all with downside [59, 60]. If we spend $1000 here, we do not spend $1000 there. We make these choices outside healthcare as a matter of routine, e.g., household expenditures, public schools, city infrastructure, social supports. Neonatology is not exempt from evidence-based, population health priority-setting [61, 62].

Author B: Physicians are not economists. We should be cognizant of resource utilization, but our proper focus is caring for the patients in our presence with the resources at our disposal. Peter Singer’s “drowning child” analogy is pertinent. We would all save a nearby child, even if it meant ruining expensive shoes by stepping into water, yet we might neglect a child dying from famine in a distant part of the world.

Author A: Health equity is social justice, an aspiration more vogue than reality. In the United States, we rationalize organ transplants in senior citizens, expensive genetic treatments for rare disorders, and high six-figure dollar expenditures for extremely premature infants, yet require families to pay for prenatal and well child visits, routine birth care, immunizations, effective medications, and emergency care. Extreme prematurity’s peculiar admixture of unproven interventions, unrestrained technology, uncertain outcomes, and disruptive financial costs consistently imperil family well-being, thus palliative care should not be oversimplified as cost-cutting [62,63,64,65,66].

Author B: Infant mortality in Canada was 4.4 per 1000 live births in 2019. The rate was 16.7 in the territory Nunavut compared to 4.5 in the province Ontario [67]. This discrepancy objectifies healthcare inequity, is unchanged over the past 20 years, and suggests injustice. Every human life has value and the rising survival rates of extremely preterm infants over this same 20 years is considered testimonial (Additional file 1: Table S1). How do we reconcile improved survival of extremely preterm infants amidst widely discrepant subpopulation rates?

Author A: Extremely premature birth is a significant health risk for pregnant women [68, 69]. Cesarean section rates are reported as 31% and 69% in 22–23 week and 24–25 week infants respectively [54]. Obstetricians’ fundamental duty is to protect the autonomy and well-being of pregnant women first-and-foremost, and to avoid unreasonable health risks thrust upon them by neonatal intensive care.

Author B: Protecting the autonomy and health of our patients is a given. If the pregnant woman is not healthy, the fetus will be adversely affected. Studies regarding routine cesarean section in extreme prematurity do not provide risk–benefit clarity, complicating uncertainty about providing palliative care or intensive care for the infant [70]. Shared decision-making should be used to support the pregnant woman regarding cesarean section decisions if intensive care is going to be provided to the infant [11, 12, 30, 71].

Author A: Because the majority of 22–23 week infants and many 24 week infants who receive intensive care either die in the neonatal intensive care unit (NICU) or survive with significant neurodevelopmental impairment and chronic health problems (Additional file 1: Table S1), NICUs and physicians who actively promote or mandate care at these extremes should do so without charges to insurers, the government, or families, whatever the outcome. This would add credibility to programs that describe their model as “proactive” or a “positive approach” [53, 54].

Author B: Is it eugenic to deny life-sustaining therapy to extremely premature infants at a certain gestational age? Choosing to provide care only to select patients without accepting that one may be wrong and causing harm by this choice carries an undesired sense of infallibility. Framing palliative care as negative versus intensive care as positive is mistaken. It is incongruous with the expanding availability of medical assistance in dying, choosing death in the face of suffering and impairment. Is there justification for pregnant women to exercise surrogate authority to allow their extremely preterm infant to die while some societies also allow autonomous adults to choose euthanasia? Do we have enough certainty about “best interests” for each extremely preterm infant such that we should override this surrogate authority?

Author A: NICUs with high rates of palliative care or conversely intensive care for 22–24 weeks infants should be transparent if and how authentic shared decision-making occurs. This is unequivocally recommended by authoritative consensus statements [12, 30, 71]. Hospitals that do not provide palliative care, or alternatively intensive care, at 22–24 weeks should offer the option of safe transfer of the pregnant woman to a hospital that honors her well-being and informed choice.

Author B: The difficulty with high-risk care is some pregnant women cannot safely be transferred because of unstable clinical factors. These women will potentially deliver at a hospital that cannot necessarily honor informed choice, or might be unable to provide the chosen option for certain clinical conditions due to expertise, staffing, and/or equipment. Undesirable mortality and morbidity might result.

Author A: Physicians are no more rational nor impartial than the general citizenry. We warrant the same scrutiny as politicians, scientists, philosophers, educators, et cetera. Humans like something and call it “good”, not the opposite [24, 25, 27]. Physicians and bioethicists should recognize there are no objective, ideal, nor supernatural “truths” existent in Nature, religion, science, or philosophy to guide ethical behavior [16, 18, 21]. Civilized society does its collective best by using pragmatic means of reason, justice, compassion, and dialogics [16, 19, 20]. Scientism and technology should not provide cover for hierarchical, unreasonable ideologies. We regrettably disguise our biased prescriptions as descriptions, cloaking our anxiety and uncertainty with opinion disguised as special facts that we alone understand [37, 72, 73].

Author B: Ideally, equipoise characterizes care options for extremely preterm infants—some view intensive care as an uncontrolled experiment, others view palliative care as discriminatory [74,75,76] (Table 1). If we provide pregnant women the opportunity to participate in comprehensive, longitudinal research studying decision-making, long-term health outcomes, and family sentiments then we might overcome inherent biases, and promote compassion and justice. We particularly need inquiry regarding women and families whose infants received palliative care, and how this compares to those whose infant received intensive care.

Conclusion

Suffering is the universal constant of human experience. How and why we minimize needless anguish yet nurture our will-to-flourish is paramount in a civilized society [16, 77]. Humanity draws inspiration from diverse philosophies, religions, science, literature, quantum physics, and more. We believe these all authenticate the singular wisdom of dialogics—the cosmopolitan ability to communicate, learn, and adjust that does not necessitate immediate consensus nor solutions [78,79,80].

We have highlighted respectful pragmatism and value pluralistic mind-sets of well-being that are the subsequence of interactive relationships. The purpose is to nurture a more collective consciousness, rather than dogma or mythical objective truths, within and between bioethicists and physicians. Dialogics incorporate suffering as unavoidable, but also as a foundation for living with extremely premature birth controversies. Human will-to-flourish is an individual impetus and yet a communal opportunity to grow, recognizing we are inherently social beings. Dialogics is that rarest of ethical constructs – both a means and an end, categorically of vital importance.

Availability of data and materials

All data generated or analyzed during this study are included in this published article.

Abbreviations

NICU:

Neonatal intensive care unit

References

  1. Gillam L. The zone of parental discretion: an ethical tool for dealing with disagreement between parents and doctors about medical treatment of a child. Clin Ethics. 2016;11(1):1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Stiggelbout AM, Pieterse AH, De Haes JC. Shared decision making: concepts, evidence, and practice. Patient Educ Couns. 2015;98:1172–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Silverman WA. The line between knowing and doing: medicine’s dilemma at the end of the twentieth century. Arch Dis Child. 1994;71:261–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Myrhaug HT, Brurberg KG, Hov L, Markestad T. Survival and impairment of extremely premature infants: a meta-analysis. Pediatrics. 2019;143(2): e20180933.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Kipnis K. Harm and uncertainty in newborn intensive care. Theor Med Bioeth. 2007;28:393–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Tyson JE, Stoll BJ. Evidence-based ethics and the care of extremely premature infants. Clin Perinatol. 2003;30:363–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Tannsjo T. Should parents of neonates with bleak prognoses be encouraged to opt for another child with better odds? On the notion of moral replaceability. Pediatrics. 2018;142(s1):e20180478F.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Boss RD, Henderson CM, Wilfond BS. Decisions regarding resuscitation of extremely premature infants: Should social context matter? J Am Med Assoc Pediatr. 2015;169(6):521–2.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Gillam L, Wilkinson D, Xafis V, Isaacs D. Decision-making at the borderline of viability: who should decide and on what basis? J Pediatr Child Health Care. 2017;53:105–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Kidszun A, Matheisl D, Tippmann S, et al. Effect of neonatal estimates on decision-making preferences of mothers facing preterm birth: a randomized clinical trial. J Am Med Assoc Pediatr. 2020;174(7):721–2.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Sullivan A, Cummings C. Shared decision making in the NICU. NeoReviews. 2020;21(4):e217–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Raju TNK, Mercer BM, Joseph GF. Periviable birth: executive summary of a joint workshop by the Eunice Kennedy shriver national institute of child health and human development, society for maternal-fetal medicine, American academy of pediatrics, and American college of obstetricians and gynecologists. J Perinatol. 2014;34:333–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Wilkinson D, Savulescu J. Ethics, conflict and medical treatment for children: from disagreement to dissensus. Edinburgh: Elsevier; 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Harrison H. The offer they can’t refuse: parents and perinatal treatment decisions. Semin Fetal Neonatal Med. 2008. https://doi.org/10.1016/siny.2008.03.004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Kaempf JW, Dirksen K. Extremely premature birth, informed written consent, and the Greek ideal of sophrosyne. J Perinatol. 2018;38:306–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Barzun J. From Dawn to Decadence: 500 years of Western Cultural Life 1500 to the present. New York: HarperCollins Publishers; 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Berlin I. The Crooked Timber of Humanity. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 1990.

  18. Rorty R. Philosophy and Social Hope. London: Penguin Books; 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Bakhtin MM. The Dialogic Imagination. In: Holquist M, editor. Austin: University of Texas Press; 1981.

  20. Bohm D. On Dialogue. In Nichol L, editor. London: Routledge; 1996.

  21. Grayling AC. The History of Philosophy. New York: Penguin Press; 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Farnsworth W. Classical English Style. Boston: David R. Godine Publisher; 2020.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Morson GS. The Long and Short of It: From Aphorism to Novel. Stanford: Stanford University Press; 2012.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  24. Haidt J. The Righteous Mind: Why Good People are Divided by Politics and Religion. New York: Rutgers University Press; 2012.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Nagel T. Types of intuition. Lond Rev Books. 2021;43(11):3–8.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Rovelli C. Helgoland: Making Sense of the Quantum Revolution. London: Penguin Random House Ltd; 2021.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Berlin I. The Proper Study of Mankind. New York: Farrar, Strauss, and Giroux; 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Menand L. The Metaphysical Club. New York: Farrar, Strauss, and Giroux; 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  29. de Beauvoir S. The Ethics of Ambiguity. New York: Kensington Publishing Corporation; 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Lemyre B, Moore G. Canadian paediatric society fetus and newborn committee. Counselling and management for anticipated extremely preterm birth. Paediatr Child Health. 2017;22(6):334–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Orr RD, Genesen LB. Requests for “inappropriate” treatment based on religious beliefs. J Med Ethics. 1997;23:142–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Safransky R. Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Nihilism GN. Nihilism. Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press; 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of Biomedical Ethics. 6th ed. New York: Oxford University Press; 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Frankfurt HG. On Bullshit. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 2005.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  36. Tucker Edmonds B, Torke AM, Helft P, Wocial LD. Doctor, what would you do? An ANSWER for patients requesting advice about value-laden decisions. Pediatrics. 2015;136(4):740–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Kaufmann W. Critique of Religion and Philosophy. Garden City: Anchor Books; 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Moore GP, Lemyre B, Daboval T, et al. Field testing of decision coaching with a decision aid for parents facing extreme prematurity. J Perinatol. 2017;37(6):728–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Staub K, Baardnes J, Hébert N, et al. Our child is not just a gestational age. A first-hand account of what parents want and need to know before premature birth. Acta Paediatr. 2014;103(10):1035–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Zaretsky R. The Subversive Simone Weil. Chicago: University of Chicago Press; 2021.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Paris JJ, Cummings BM, Moore MP. Compassion and mercy are not helpful in resolving intractable family-physician conflicts of interest on end-of-life care. J Perinatol. 2019;39:11–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. De Proost L, Verweij EJT, Ismaili M’hamdi H, et al. The edge of perinatal viability: understanding the Dutch position. Front Pediatr. 2021;9:634290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Grady C. Enduring and emerging challenges of informed consent. N Engl J Med. 2015;372(9):855–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Silverman WA. Where’s the Evidence? Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  45. McHaffie HE, Laing IA, Parker M, McMillan J. Deciding for imperiled newborns: medical authority or parental autonomy? J Med Ethics. 2001;27(2):104–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. Guillen U, Suh S, Munson D, et al. Development and pretesting of a decision-aid to use when counseling parents facing imminent extreme premature delivery. J Pediatr. 2012;160(3):382–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Veatch RM. Implied, presumed, and waived consent: the relative moral wrongs of under- and over-informing. Am J Bioeth. 2007;7(12):39–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Kaempf JW, Guillen UG, Litt JS, Zupancic JAF, Kirpalani H. Change in neurodevelopmental outcomes for extremely premature infants over time: a systematic review and meta-analysis. Arch Dis Childhood Fetal Neonatal Edn. 2022. https://doi.org/10.1136/archdischild-2022-324457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Ni Y, O’Reilly H, Johnson S, Marlow N, Wolke D. Health related quality of life from adolescence to adulthood following extremely preterm birth. J Pediatr. 2021;237:227–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Batsvik B, Vederhus BJ, Halvorsen T, Wentzel-Larsen T, Graue M, Markestad T. Health-related quality of life may deteriorate from adolescence to young adulthood after extremely preterm birth. Acta Paediatr. 2015;104:948–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Gire C, Resseguier N, Brevaut-Malaty V, et al. Quality of life of extremely preterm school-age children without major handicap: a cross-sectional observational study. Arch Dis Child. 2019;104:333–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Saigal S, Ferro MA, Van Lieshout RJ, Schmidt LA, Morrison KM, Boyle MH. Health-related quality of life trajectories of extremely low birth weight survivors into adulthood. J Pediatr. 2016;179:68–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Rysavy MA, Li L, Bell EF, et al. Between-hospital variation in treatment and outcomes in extremely premature infants. N Engl J Med. 2015;372(19):1801–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Watkins PL, Dagle JM, Bell EF, Colaizy TT. Outcomes at 18 to 22 months of corrected age for infants born at 22 to 25 weeks of gestation in a center practicing active management. J Pediatr. 2020;217:52-58.e1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Harris LH. Divisions, new and old—conscience and religious freedom at HHS. N Engl J Med. 2018;378(15):1369–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. Cavolo A, de Casterle BD, Naulaers G, Gastmans C. Physicians’ attitudes on resuscitation of extremely premature infants: a systematic review. Pediatrics. 2019;143(6): e20183972.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. Wilkinson D. Sleep softly: Schubert, ethics and the value of dying well. J Med Ethics. 2020;47(4):218–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. McGee A. Moral status of babies. J Med Ethics. 2013;39:345–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. Rawlins MD. Cost, effectiveness, and value: how to judge? J Am Med Assoc. 2016;316(14):1447–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  60. Chua KP, Conti RM, Freed GL. Appropriately framing child health care spending: a prerequisite for value improvement. J Am Med Assoc. 2018;319(11):1087–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  61. Ord T. The moral imperative toward cost-effectiveness in global health. Center for Global Development. March 2013. Accessed Sept 2021. www.cgdev.org/content/publications/detail/1427016.

  62. Beam AL, Fried I, Palmer N, et al. Estimates for healthcare spending for preterm and low-birthweight infants in a commercially insured population. J Perinatol. 2020;40:1091–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  63. Hay S, Mowitz M, Dukhovny D, et al. Unbiasing costs? An appraisal of economic assessment alongside randomized trials in neonatology. Semin Perinatol. 2021;45: 151391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  64. Helgesson G. It is not ethical to save an infant’s life just because we can, without due regard to outcome. Acta Paediatr. 2017;107(2):194–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  65. Lonnqvist P. Number needed to suffer: replying to comments on my paper. Acta Paediatr. 2018;107:204–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  66. Waitzman NJ, Jalali A, Grosse SD. Preterm birth lifetime costs in the United States in 2016: an update. Semin Perinatol. 2021;45: 151390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  67. Statistics Canada. Table 13-10–0713-01. Infant deaths and mortality rates, by age group. Accessed Sept 2021. https://doi.org/10.25318/1310071301-eng.

  68. Lannon SM, Guthrie KA, Vanderhoeven JP, Gammill HS. Uterine rupture after periviable cesarean delivery. Obstet Gynecol. 2015;125:1095–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  69. Blanc J, Resseguier N, Goffinet F, et al. Association between gestational age and severe maternal morbidity and mortality of preterm cesarean delivery: a population-based cohort study. Am J Obstet Gynecol. 2019;220(4):399.e1-399.e9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  70. Jarde A, Feng YY, Viaje KA, Shah PS, McDonald SD. Vaginal birth vs caesarean section for extremely preterm vertex infants: a systematic review and meta-analyses. Arch Gynecol Obstet. 2020;301(2):447–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  71. Cummings JA. Antenatal counseling regarding resuscitation and intensive care before 25 weeks gestation. Committee on fetus and newborn clinical report. Pediatrics. 2015;136(3):588–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  72. Midgley M. The Essential Mary Midgley. In: David Midgley editors. New York: Routledge; 2005.

  73. Kaplan A. The new world of philosophy. New York: Vintage Books; 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Lucey JF, Rowan CA, Shiono P, et al. Fetal infants: the fate of 4172 infants with birth weights of 401 to 500 grams – the Vermont Oxford Network experience (1996–2000). Pediatrics. 2004;113(6):1559–1566.Krutch JW. The Modern Temper. New York, NY, USA: Harcourt, Brace, and Company; 1956.

  75. Janvier A, Lantos J. Delivery room practices for extremely preterm infants: the harms of the gestational age label. Arch Dis Childhood Fetal Neonatal Edn. 2016;101(5):F375-376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  76. Kaempf JW, Tomlinson MW, Tuohey J. Extremely premature birth and the choice of neonatal intensive care versus palliative comfort care: an 18-year single center experience. J Perinatol. 2016;36:190–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  77. Muller HJ. The uses of the past: profiles of former societies. New York: Oxford University Press; 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Corngold S. Walter Kauffmann: Philosopher, Humanist, Heretic. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 2019.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  79. Cioran EM. The temptation to exist. New York: Arcade Publishing; 1956.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Lau T, Tao Te Ching, Lau DC. Translator. London: Penguin Books; 1963.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are grateful to the many authors in Additional file 1: Table S1, and the contributors to our diverse references, whose diligent work and analysis have furthered understanding of the myriad effects of extremely premature birth upon pregnant women, their families, healthcare providers, and society.

Funding

JWK work was supported in part by the Providence Foundation and Providence Women and Children’s Services. Providence Health System had no role in the study conception, literature review or selection, data summary, or conclusions of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

JWK and GPM designed the work, reviewed the referenced material, and have read and approved the final version of the manuscript, agreeing to be personally accountable for their contributions and the integrity of the work.

Authors’ information

JWK is the Medical Director of Value, Research, and Innovation for Women and Children’s Services in the Providence Health System of Oregon. JWK completed his internship and residency training in Pediatrics at The Johns Hopkins Hospital in Baltimore, MD, and additional fellowship training in Neonatal-Perinatal Medicine at the University of Colorado Health Sciences Center in Denver, CO. He has practiced neonatology and hospital pediatrics since 1989. GPM is an academic neonatologist, practicing at CHEO and The Ottawa Hospital in Ottawa, ON, Canada. He is an associate professor on the clinician-teacher path in the Faculty of Medicine at uOttawa. He has his BSc from Queen’s University (Kingston, ON, Canada), MD from Western (London, ON, Canada), FRCPC in Pediatrics and Neonatal-Perinatal Medicine from uOttawa (Ottawa, ON, Canada), additional one year clinical fellowship year in Neonatal-Perinatal Medicine from the Royal Women’s Hospital (Melbourne, VIC, Australia) and MSt in Practical Ethics from University of Oxford (Oxford, UK).

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joseph W. Kaempf.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate

Not applicable.

Consent for publication

Not applicable.

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Supplementary Information

Additional file 1

: Table S1. 2016–2022 summary of recent neurodevelopmental follow-up studies of extremely premature infants.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated in a credit line to the data.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kaempf, J.W., Moore, G.P. Extremely premature birth bioethical decision-making supported by dialogics and pragmatism. BMC Med Ethics 24, 9 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-023-00887-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-023-00887-z

Keywords