Skip to main content
  • Research article
  • Open access
  • Published:

Among equity and dignity: an argument-based review of European ethical guidelines under COVID-19

Abstract

Background

Under COVID-19 pandemic, many organizations developed guidelines to deal with the ethical aspects of resources allocation. This study describes the results of an argument-based review of ethical guidelines developed at the European level. It aims to increase knowledge and awareness about the moral relevance of the outbreak, especially as regards the balance of equity and dignity in clinical practice and patient’s care.

Method

According to the argument-based review framework, we started our research from the following two questions: what are the ethical principles adopted by the ethical guidelines produced at the beginning of the COVID-19 outbreak related to resource allocation? And what are the practical consequences in terms of 'priority' of access, access criteria, management of the decision-making process and patient care?

Results

Twenty-two ethical guidelines met our inclusion criteria and the results of our analysis are organized into 4 ethical concepts and related arguments: the equity principle and emerging ethical theories; triage criteria; respecting patient’s dignity, and decision making and quality of care.

Conclusion

Further studies can investigate the practical consequences of the application of the guidelines described, in terms of quality of care and health care professionals’ moral distress.

Peer Review reports

Background

After the spread of the novel severe acute respiratory syndrome coronavirus 2 (SARS-CoV-2) and the related COronaVIrus Disease 2019 (COVID-19), many national health care systems had to deal with a dramatic re-organization of services. At the beginning of the outbreak, COVID-19 positive patients with severe illness required highly specialized care, such as mechanical ventilation and extracorporeal membrane oxygenation, which were not readily available or not applicable to a significant number of cases [1,2,3]. Moreover, the scarce availability of intensive care unit (ICU) beds is common all over the word [4]. It forces health care professionals and health care organizations to continuously balance the principle of patient-centered care, the focus of clinical ethics under normal conditions, and that of public-focused duty to promote equality of persons, which is the focus of public health ethics [5]. More than usual, the spread of Covid-19 highlighted this difficult balancing.

In a short time, the hardest-hit countries, China, USA, Italy and Spain [3, 4] had to deal with issues of allocation of scarce resource. Rationing intensive care beds or specialized services has clinical and ethical implications. The “decision about initiating or terminating mechanical intervention is often truly a life-or-death choice” [7], even if, in the case of Covid-19, data have shown uncertainty regarding the efficacy of mechanical ventilation as the outbreak has progressed [8]. However, the allocation of intensive care treatments remains crucial.

The central question regards how to establish a fair resource allocation and how to guarantee that the decisions are made “ethically and consistently, rather than based on individual institution’s approaches or a clinician's institution in the heat of the moment” [9].

Resource allocation is a crucial ethical issue because it most fundamentally involves questions of justice. The identification and definition of an equal distribution of resources, opportunities and outcomes among the population represent a concern for national governments and health care facilities. Due to the nature of the pandemic itself, this ethical issue reached a global dimension.

According to the World Health Organization (WHO) [9], developing guidelines on the allocation of scarce resources in outbreak situations require governments, health-care facilities and other involved in such effort to consider the tension between the principles of utility (allocating resources to maximize benefit and minimize burdens) and equity (fair distribution of benefit and burdens); the definition of utility; the needs of vulnerable populations; the fulfillment of reciprocity-based obligations and the provision of supportive and palliative care. The principle of equity in access to health care plays a central role in fair allocation: it “must be upheld, because it lays down in the respect for human dignity and human right framework” (namely, Article 3 of the Oviedo Convention and article 14 of the Unesco Declaration on Bioethics and Human rights, 2005) even in a context of scarce resources [10, 11].

There are multiple ethically permissible approaches to allocating scarce life-sustaining resources, but these theories yield conflicting definitions. For instance, utilitarianism focuses on the maximization of benefit, while egalitarianism focuses on equality of opportunity and need [12].

With COVID-19, health departments, local and national clinical ethics committees, and scientific societies had urgently developed new (or have revised existing) ethical guidelines or ethical recommendations, identifying which criteria should be used to ethically allocate scarce resources and what process should be used to fairly implement allocation decisions [13].

Because the public will bear the consequences of these decisions, knowledge of perspectives and moral points of reference on these issues is critical [14]: unjustified variation could exacerbate structural inequalities, squander valuable resources and undermine public health [13, 14], as demonstrated by the debates about exclusion criteria and discrimination against age and disability that have already arisen in Italy and in the USA [15].

It can be useful to understand and compare the various ethical perspectives involved in ethical guidelines developed during COVID-19 through a full set of published reasons for or against the view in question, which is the central scope of an argument-based review [16].

This study describes the results of an argument-based review of the ethical guidelines developed at the European level to face the health care emergency at the beginning of COVID-19 pandemic.

We analyzed the underpinnings and ethical concepts, as well as their practical consequences, with the aim of increasing knowledge and awareness related to the ethical meanings of the outbreak.

Methods

The argument-based review represents one of the different methods for systematic reviews developed in the field of bioethics, and it aims to present an up-to-date comprehensive overview of the ethical arguments and underpinning concepts identified in relation to a certain topic [16,17,18]. This approach is particularly suitable for our study because it led the researchers to acquire evidence for decision-making in the delivery of healthcare, development of policy, and conduct of medical research [18].

To grasp the underpinnings of ethical theories, their principles and related practical consequences regarding the ethical aspect of allocation resources, we performed the argument-based systematic review of ethical guidelines following the model developed by McCullough et al. [16, 17].

We first articulated our research questions into two relevant conceptual ethical questions; then, we performed a literature search, and finally, we identified, described and analyzed the ethical arguments in connection with the conceptual-ethical questions.

Research questions

To understand how European countries dealt with the ethical allocation of scarce health resources at the beginning of the COVID-19 pandemic, we developed the following research questions:

  1. a.

    What are the ethical principles adopted by the ethical guidelines produced at the beginning of COVID-19 outbreak, related to resource allocation?

  2. b.

    What are the practical consequences in terms of 'priority' of access, access criteria, management of the decision-making process and patient care?

Literature search

Articles were selected based on the following predetermined eligibility criteria for their relevance to our research question:

  1. a.

    they must be guidelines or recommendation policies;

  2. b.

    they must be published between March and May 2020;

  3. c.

    they must be developed in response to the COVID-19 health emergency;

  4. d.

    they have been developed by institutions suitable to formulate such guidelines (such as local or National Ethical Committees, Health Ministerial Departments, and Scientific Societies);

  5. e.

    they explicitly deal with the allocation of resource according to an ethical framework;

  6. f.

    they have been written in English or have been translated in English.

We excluded scientific articles, editorials, book chapters and position papers. Finally, we included further publications using the snowball sampling method and gray literature research. Due to the characteristics of the search literature, we used the following resources: national ethics committee websites, scientific society websites, international organization’s websites, collecting specific ethical resources on COVID-19 (see Additional file 1—Appendix 1).

Data extraction and synthesis

We performed a qualitative analysis, adapting the Qualitative Analysis Guide of Leuven—QUAGOL [19]. It offers a comprehensive, systematic but not rigid method to guide the process of qualitative data analysis. Its characteristics lie in the iterative process of digging deeper, constantly moving between the various stages of the process [19].

MP and LDP identified the eligible ethical guidelines. They read each document entirely the first time to have an overview of the topics and relevant arguments; afterwards, they read the documents a second time, focusing specifically on: (a) the ethical framework described and (b) the section describing the allocation of scarce resources.

MP collected the relevant information of each document into a conceptual scheme. It is a synthetic frame where different and relevant concepts are presented and integrated with each others to answer the research questions [18, 19]. Each conceptual scheme highlights the relationships between the ethical framework described in the guideline, the allocation resources argumentation and their practical consequences in clinical practice and decision making process (an example of a conceptual scheme is provided as Additional file 2: Appendix 2). The schemes’ adequateness was checked by LDP.

Successively, MP unified all the schemes into a single table (Table 1) to create an overview and provide a comprehensive answer to our research questions. LDP overviewed the process. The table describes the responses to our research questions reporting the ethical principles (question 1) and practical consequences (question 2). We specified the relationships between ethical principles and practical consequences in terms of 'priority' of access, access criteria, management of the decision-making process and the emerging patient’s care (question 2).

Table 1 Ethical guidelines’ argument-based analysis: the final conceptual scheme

The documents’ full texts, their relative conceptual schemes, and the final table were iteratively evaluated and checked against previous QUAGOL steps to ensure that they were consistent.

Finally, MP and LDP synthesized a description of the results to be presented in the Results section.

Results

We collected 42 ethical guidelines, and their characteristics are described in Table 2.

Table 2 Published guidelines characteristics

The most represented are UK (7 published ethical guidelines), France (6 published guidelines) and Spain (4 published guideline), followed by Switzerland, Germany (3 published guidelines) and Italy (2 ethical guidelines). The majority of the ethical guidelines was published by Scientific Society (21 ethical guidelines) and National Ethic Committees (16 ethical guidelines). 14 ethical guidelines were published in English and 10 ethical guidelines present the English translations and could be included in our analysis. We then excluded an ethical guideline because it presented an updated version.

Finally, twenty-two ethical guidelines met our inclusion criteria and were analyzed by argument-based analysis (as reported in Table 1).

As a result of the analysis and synthesis of the 22 individual guidelines, we ultimately identified the following ethical concepts and their related arguments, as described in Table 3:

  1. 1.

    Equity principle and emerging ethical theories.

  2. 2.

    Triage criteria.

  3. 3.

    Respecting patient dignity.

  4. 4.

    Decision making and quality of care.

Table 3 Identification of the ethical concept, their related arguments and the reference’ s guideline

Equity principle and the emerging ethical theories

The analysis of the ethical guidelines highlights the central role of equity principle showing different meanings based on its theoretical relationship with three main ethical theories: egalitarianism, utilitarianism, and ethics of care.

The egalitarian approach: equity and non-discrimination

Inspired by the egalitarian approach, 14 ethical guidelines balance the principle of equity intended as equal treatment for equal needs with the principle of equality, that is equal treatment regardless of needs. The guidelines describe equality in terms of the respect for the absolute value of life and dignity of the person, as defined by the human rights framework [10, 11, 20,21,22,23,24,25,26,27]. As a result of this approach, triage criteria should be applied to every patient without discrimination or distinction among COVID and non-COVID patients [10, 11, 24,25,26, 28,29,30,31]. Following this perspective, some guidelines apply the “first come, first served” approach to choose between patients with the same urgency and needs [29, 30], even if it cannot be considered as the only criterion for allocation resources.

The utilitarian approach: equity and the best use of resources

10 guidelines balance the principle of equity with the principle of utility, which requires first to identify the type of outcomes that will be counted as improvements to the greatest common benefit. Utility principle is widely described as maximizing the benefits from scarce resources for the greatest number of people. It also consists of the “best value use” of resources [32,33,34] by reducing mortality and incrementing benefits in the society [5, 35,36,37,38]. Following the utilitarian approach, the total number of lives saved [32], the number of years of life saved [36] or the total number of years saved in relation to the quality of life and the capacity of the patient to benefit from the treatment are crucial aspects [30, 32,33,34, 37, 39]. The Italian ethical guidelines developed by the Italian Society of Anesthesia Analgesia Resuscitation and Intensive Care (SIAARTI) highlight that the “extraordinary nature of the situation” can justify the clinicians’ judgment about the inappropriate access of a patient to intensive treatment, namely to the pursuit of the greatest common benefit [36]. The Estonian ethical guidelines developed by the University of Tartu underlines that the patient-centered approach should be replaced with the community-centered approach. Consequently, physicians are not obliged to provide intensive care to a patient with a negative prognosis if that care is needed for the treatment of a patient with a better prognosis [32].

The relationship between equity principle and the ethics of care framework

15 guidelines balance the Beauchamp and Childress’ four principles of medical ethics [25, 27, 31,32,33], proportionality and appropriateness of care [24, 38, 39], and the health care professional’s responsibility to care [34]. The emerging meaning of equity in allocation resources lies in the concept of decisions taken “case by case”, without automatisms or criteria according to which the sick person would be excluded based on belonging to a category established a priori [22, 37] and providing assistance based on the needs of the individual patient, the realistic goal of care and the will of the individual concerned [21, 24,25,26, 28, 38]. This approach can be related to the ethics of care theoretical framework. It recognizes the value of each personal experience but also that human beings are interdependent [40, 41]. According to ethics of care, every moral choice or ethical issue is conceived as inserted in the relationship of care [42].

Triage criteria

To apply the allocation resources in a practical situation, the guidelines identify a set of “triage criteria”, which identify who and how patients should access or be prioritized to intensive care. The most favorable prognosis is widely considered the main criterion to prioritize patients.[43] According with the equity principle discussed above, this criterion is defined by 2 different approaches: quantitative health-related triage criteria and patient-related clinical judgment.

Quantitative health-related triage criteria

The ethical guidelines here described define the most favorable prognosis in the patient's expected treatment outcomes in terms of duration and quality of life after intensive treatment [32, 33, 35, 37, 39]. The presence of life-short chronic diseases, severe comorbidities and the disease severity are also central criteria for non admission to ICU, and they are usually assessed by score system tools (e.g., the Clinical Frailty Score) [28,29,30, 32, 33, 35,36,37].

Some guidelines include age as a possible criterion. For example, two guidelines specify that triage criteria should also be based on the appraisal of the total number of lives saved, life years saved and patient’s years of life [35, 36]. One guideline specifies the possibility to introduce an age threshold to a patient’s access to intensive care due to the extraordinary situation [36], while others specify that age cannot be considered as a criterion in itself but in relation to the current clinical evaluation [29, 33].

Following this approach and the quantity of life-related criteria, some guidelines define those categories of people who do not access treatment: the terminally ill [29], those who do not consent to treatments through Advance Directives [29, 32, 35, 36] or Advance Care Planning [28, 29, 33], and patients with specific clinical diagnoses, such as dementia or cognitive impairments [29]. In this regard, other guidelines specify that the lack of ability to give consent and disability should not be considered a discriminatory factor to access to treatment [28]. One guideline specifies that priority should be a guarantee to a specific group, namely, people at risk and people with essential responsibilities and roles in the pandemic management, due to the principle of reciprocity [35].

The majority of guidelines do not expressly distinguish between withholding and withdrawing treatments. However, according to two guidelines, the physician has the right to withdraw the ICU resources from a patient with a negative prognosis if they are needed for the treatment of a patient with a better prognosis [32, 37]. This practice is linked with the regular assessment of patients: in facts daily re-evaluation of ICU patients is required by all the guidelines to determine whether criteria to undergo intensive treatment are still met.

Patient-related clinical judgment and “questionable criteria”

A number of ethical guidelines do not apply specific health-related clinical triage criteria but adopts a more general patient-related clinical judgment [10, 21, 24,25,26,27, 30, 31, 38]. In particular, the guideline developed by the French national Consultative Ethics Committee openly affirms that criteria are always questionable [21], and the German Ethics Committee affirms that any criteria should not overcome the human rights framework [22]. Following this approach, the triage criteria are defined by a case-by-case assessment of the patient’s clinical condition [25] and should take into consideration the urgency, the severity of comorbidity, the proportionality and appropriateness of the invasive treatments, and the treatment’s prognostic efficacy in terms of probable healing [24,25,26, 28,29,30]. Timely identification of disproportionate care is also required [29], and there is not an obligation to provide treatment which is not clinically appropriate [38]. In this regard, futility, proportionality or disproportionate care emerged among the ethical guidelines as criteria for withholding treatments and redirecting the therapeutic goal towards palliative care, only when ICU treatments are considered no more beneficial for the patient him/herself.

Moreover the health care professionals’ duty of care, which is linked to the ethics of solidarity between them and members of society [44], is also considered a relevant aspect to apply triage criteria in such a situation. Ethical guidelines underline clinicians’ responsibility to timely inform patients and their families about triage criteria and, principally, the responsibility to promote a discussion about the patient’s access to intensive care with timely advanced care planning [28,29,30, 33].

Ethically unacceptable criteria and controversial application

The majority of the guidelines report a set of ethically unacceptable criteria, including gender, ethnicity, sexual orientation, religion and political vision. They are justified on the basis of the equality principle with respect to human dignity and the human rights framework [22, 24, 28, 30, 32, 35]. Most of the guidelines place specific attention on age, which cannot be assumed as the only criterion [26, 29, 33], and disability [24, 28, 30, 39]; these groups are considered vulnerable people, and specific attention and particular effort should be made to ensure them equal rights and treatments [11].

Despite this, it is important to point out that there is controversy on the age issue. For example, the Swiss ethical guideline, while declaring to avoid any discrimination based on age, uses the age limit as an exclusion criteria in certain situation [33]. The Belgian document states that age in isolation cannot be used for triage decisions, but should be integrated with other clinical parameters: frailty and reduced cognition. They are specifically described as ‘independent predictors of outcome when elderly patients are admitted to the ICU’, but, as mentioned above, they would be effective only in combination with age [29].

Respecting patient dignity

Respecting human dignity is a central aspect of the analyzed guidelines.

While the term ‘dignity’ is cited in each guideline, no explicit description of its meaning is provided. However, the general significance of dignity arose, and it can be described in terms of respecting the intrinsic value of each human beings (equality) while differentiating resources among people with different needs (equity) (Table 4).

Table 4 Emerging meaning of dignity among ethical guidelines

Moreover, ethical guidelines describe how to respect dignity through the application of palliative care, consideration of patients’ wills, and an individualized patient care.

Palliative care

Most of the guidelines include the provision of palliative care for all patients who will not receive ICU treatments. Two ethical guidelines explicitly argue that palliative care represents an approach to respect human dignity: people affected by a serious illness does not lose their intrinsic value as a person nor the right to be supported and protected [24, 34]. Patients who do not meet the triage criteria and cannot accede to intensive treatments, patients at the end of life, or patients who refuse the intervention should all be referred to palliative care, which aims to ensure a death without suffering and proximity to the family, despite the difficulties imposed by the situation [24, 26, 28, 34,35,36,37]. Some guidelines emphasize that patients who do not accede to the intensive treatment (or the ones whose treatments should be withdrawn) have the right to receive the best available alternative and compassionate care, that lies in the principle of continuity of care [11, 28, 30, 33, 37], and is supported by the principle of justice [35].

Considering the patient’s will and wishes

Another emerging way to respect patient dignity is dealing with patient’s will. A significant number of ethical guidelines include that physicians should take into consideration patient’s Advance Directives and his/her consent to intensive treatment or other treatment. Knowing the patient’s will and discussing the possibility of invasive treatment are associated with respect for the patient’s autonomy and moral values underlined by the 4 principles of medical ethics [28, 29, 32, 33]. The patient’s will represents a tool to help clinicians to make triage decisions and should be carefully evaluated in advance [29, 32, 34,35,36].

Individualized patient care

Some ethical guidelines highlight the necessity to provide individualized and person-centered care, even in the context of a public health emergency. This approach requires paying attention to vulnerabilities and to differentiating treatment considering the individual needs of each patient as the optimal way to avoid discrimination in access to health care [10, 21, 25, 26, 28, 30]. It develops the consideration that all patients should be offered good quality and compassionate care and treated as individuals, while recognizing that there may be a competing obligation to the wider population [11, 27, 38]. According to this approach, ICU treatments would be interrupted or not initiated only if they are considered not beneficial for the individual patient.

The communicative aspects of care and its implication on patients and familiars are also important for strengthening the care relationship [31, 32, 36, 38]. As specifically noted in the ethical guidelines provided by the General Medical Council, the health care professions should communicate openly and honestly with patients and the rest of the health care team about the decision-making process and the criteria for establishing priorities in individual cases [34].

Decision making and quality of care

The decision-making process for allocation of resources is a frequent element of all guidelines. It is also built on ethical principles and represents an important aspect to ensure high-quality care and to strengthen the health care relationship, even in the urgency context. The institution of ethics support and ethics committee (or any other form of support for health care professionals) are also frequently required.

Ethical aspects of communication and triage management

Transparency, reasonableness, inclusiveness, openness and the uniform application of triage criteria at the different levels of care are important reference principles to ensure the non-arbitrariness of the final decision [11, 22, 25, 26, 37]. Procedures for decision making should respect human dignity [11], and clinicians should act with honesty and integrity [38]. The involvement of health care professionals not directly involved in the provision of intensive care is also underlined to mitigate the negative effects of pressure on doctors and teams [25], and a collective decision made by an ad hoc medical committee is often required [34, 36, 39]. An on-going revision of the guidelines, triage criteria and decisions is also a reiterated aspect to ensure that the best possible treatments are always guaranteed to each patient [36, 37].

Need of ethical support

Since these are very difficult decisions, the presence of local ethics committees, ethicists, or any other form of support, including psychological, aimed at managing and reducing the moral distress of health care professionals [21, 25, 28,29,30, 32, 34, 36, 37], is considered as an important aid for distributing and strengthening their sense of responsibility, applying ethical guidelines in their daily practice and, finally, making difficult decisions and facing direct dilemmas, especially in those extremely complex situations where suspension of already initiated treatments is required. Ethical guidelines have also noted that the application of a structured decision-making process and the identification of the persons responsible for the decision are fundamental to guarantee the patient, his family members and the community itself the trust pact and alliance on which the relationship of care is based and that the current emergency could dramatically corrupt [21].

Discussion

The purpose of our study was to analyze how the European countries dealt with the allocation of scarce clinical resources at the beginning of the COVID-19 pandemic. We analyzed the ethical concepts and their practical consequences described in the ethical guidelines developed under COVID-19 by different institutional bodies (such as national ethics committees and health departments) among the European countries.

Our results are in line with similar articles comparing ethical guidelines developed under COVID-19 [43, 45, 46]. Differently from them, our analysis compared an higher number of guidelines and emphasized all the relevant ethical approaches, such as ethics of care and individualized patient care.

Each guideline analyzed recognizes respect for each human life's intrinsic value and the value of health as a human right as milestones to implement respect for human dignity.

Specifically, the emerging meaning of dignity is the intrinsic value of all the individuals who share the essential properties of human beings (“intrinsic dignity”). In recognition of that value, the health care professionals have a moral duty towards those who are suffering from disease and injury [47]. According with Jobgsen et al., the reference to equality and equity principle represents an area of consensus among European guidelines, and consequently the respect for human dignity lies in the principle of equal worth of people [45].

Nevertheless, during a pandemic, also the value of maximizing benefit emerged as an area of consensus [45]. Our results highlighted an implicit tension between respect for the equal right to health and risk of taking triage decision, including potential discriminatory criteria (such as patient’s frailty, short-term prognosis and cognitive impairment, which are linked to age). Then, the risk of applying a strictly utilitarian approach emerged, even if it was not a predominant approach for allocating resources among European guidelines [43]. This utilitarian consideration is most important, according to other non-European ethical guidelines, and in particular with American [9, 13] and Australian [48] guidelines. As noted by Emanuel et al., priority for limited resources should aim “both at saving the most lives and at maximizing improvements in individuals’ post treatment length of life”, which is “consistent both with utilitarian ethical perspective, focused on population outcomes, and with non-utilitarian views which emphasize the paramount value of each human life” [9]. The patient’s benefit and post-treatment outcomes are frequently cited in the European guidelines. It is often supported [5, 49, 50] the duty to care as the responsibility to respect the rights of patients to autonomy, transparency, privacy, and confidentiality of personal informations. These guidelines also require that procedures for taking informed consent and advance directives shall be observed and, where appropriate, legally authorized substitute decision-makers shall be consulted. Different from our results, the last guideline provided by The Hastings Center [51] affirms that an ethical allocation resource strategy first requires the protection of health care workers delivering care in the midst of the crisis, for without them and their extraordinary efforts, the entire health system would collapse. Subsequently, decisions about who receives treatment must center on prevention of SARS-CoV-2 transmission (public health), protection of individuals at highest risk, meeting societal needs, and promoting social justice [51]. Consequently, groups at highest risk, such as older adults, people with compromised immune systems, and people with underlying conditions (such as heart or lung diseases or diabetes) are another priority, as they are most likely to become seriously ill and die. This is in line with the concept of taking care of vulnerable groups, which was also underlined in our results.

Previous studies [52, 53] related to end-of –life care practices in ICU, highlight that decisions on withholding and withdrawing intensive treatments are mostly affected by patient age, acute and chronic diagnosis, number of days in ICU and cultural and religious beliefs [53]. Only 4 [28, 29, 35, 36] guidelines on COVID-19 pandemic are in line with those results, while a high number of guidelines underlined the importance of the individualized approach. It is essential to mention the difference between an acute and chronic diagnosis and COVID-19 illness. While in the first case can be clear what is overtreatment and the meaning of deterioration, during COVID-19 rapid deterioration does not necessary correspond to end of life, and thracheostomy can save the patient’s life. Consequently, short terms survival should be considered cautiously because it is not yet well known in Covid-19 [45].

Our results emphasize the need to respect the patient’s choices and will through advanced discussion on the access to intensive care and open and transparent communication about triage criteria. This reflects the attempt of health care professionals in non-pandemic situations to take individualized decision on the access to ICU, accordingly with clinical judgment and patient’s goals of care [54]. The importance of patient’s advance directives and patient’s will and the explicit recommendation to offer palliative care to patients whose treatment is withdrawn or withheld represent a consensus area among European ethical guideline [43, 45].

Despite our results recognize the value of both personalized care and relationship of care, many concerns regarding the effective possibility to respect patient’s consent and will arise in clinical practice, above all in pandemic situations: as noted by Angelos P et al., as scarcities increase, clinicians will increasingly be in a position in which they cannot respect all of their patient’s wishes, leading them to assume a paternalistic approach [55].

According to this study, the discussion of prognosis is central to obtaining informed consent for intubation, but, as noted by Zareifopoulos et al., in the absence of definitive data, it is not clear exactly what this discussion should entail [56]. Moreover, one of our guidelines affirms that the clinician’s judgment of inappropriateness would be justified by the critical situation’s extraordinariness, which reflects a paternalistic approach. This is in line also with Emanuel et al., who confirm that in a critical situation “the decision to withdraw a scarce resource to save others is not an act of killing and does not require the patient’s consent” [9].

According with similar studies [43, 45], our results show that the European ethical guidelines are very sensitive to the risk of discrimination arising from strict triage criteria, and particularly regarding age and disability. The difficult choices regarding admission to ICU of patients with advanced disease or elderly patients with multiple comorbidities was considered a ‘grey zone’ also in non-pandemic situations [54]. Discrimination based on age correlates the maximum benefit obtainable with the prioritization of younger people over old people, who have less life expectancy (both in terms of quantity and quality) and have already lived much more than young people [57]. This is widely spread among the American and Mexican ethical guidelines [58]. Particularly, White and Lo, 2020 justify “ageism” on the number of year saved [59], while the American Society of Geriatrics (ASG) assesses that rationing strategies that are based in part on age cutoffs could lead to persistent beliefs that older adults’ lives are less valuable than others’ lives or are even expendable [23].

Fighting the ageistic approach, Cesari and al. 2020 replaced the age criterion for the allocation of resources with a parameter more robust than age but equally easy to obtain and that can be used for critical and rapid decision-making, namely, the careful evaluation of the presence of comorbidity and functional status in addition to age. This is also marked by Auriemma et al. 2020 [59], who argue that an optimal policy for critical care resource allocation should not use categorical exclusions, in order to mitigate discrimination: ‘the feasibility virtues offered by such coarse systems are readily outweighed by their threats to justice, public trust, and clinician morale’. When the decision of using a ventilator for a person with respiratory distress is based on his/her birth date or other categorical exclusion criteria “we must realize that modern medicine may be at risk of having lost the meaning and value of the human life” [60].

Compared to European concerns, in the United States, the discussion on resource allocation and triage criteria dealt more deeply with issues of potential unjust discrimination for specific citizen group (namely elderly and disables). It  led to an open discussion and public engagement process to ensure equal access to health care that failed among European countries [46]. European ethical guidelines have been developed mainly by professionals societies or national bodies, resulting in a total lack of public involvement in identifying and discussing the principles that could guide scarce resources allocation.

Our results mention the importance of trust communication among health care professionals and patients and their familiars. The inclusion of a patient’s representative in developing ethical guidelines could improve health care professionals to make well-founded decisions in the interest of their patients.

As noted by Mannelli, the novelty of the current emergency has to do with the extraordinarily high number of people who find themselves personally affected by the implications of scarce resources allocation and who suddenly realize that the principle of “equals should be treated equally” may no longer be applicable [2].

Conclusion

According to the ethical guidelines developed at the beginning of the COVID-19 pandemic, promoting how to figure out a way to personalize care during COVID-19 still represents a moral duty [5]. Being guided by the ethical reflection that considers respect for persons' dignity and the principle of equity, the difficult choices regarding patient prioritization and allocation of scarce resources should avoid unfair discrimination. At the same time, this kind of ethical reflection guarantees a relational approach to ethics, which includes appropriate and proportionate care, transparency and trust communication and, mostly, considering interconnection, vulnerability and shared humanity [44]. Personalized care in such a critical situation develops concretely by (a) a multidisciplinary, multidimensional and individualized evaluation of each patient; (b) the contextualization of ethical guidelines, involving who is directly called to their application; (c) an effective palliative care approach; and (d) the implementation of clinical ethics support, which represents a very important resource to help health care professionals in making difficult decisions [61].

Further studies can investigate the practical consequences of the application of the guidelines described in terms of quality of care and health care professionals’ moral distress.

Availability of data and materials

All data generated or analysed during this study are included in this published article (and its supplementary information files).

Abbreviations

SARS-CoV-2:

Severe acute respiratory syndrome coronavirus 2

COVID-19:

COronaVirus Disease 2019

ICU:

Intensive Care Unit

WHO:

World Health Organization

QUAGOL:

Qualitative Analysis Guide of Leuven

SIAARTI:

Italian Society of Anesthesia Analgesia Resuscitation and Intensive Care

ASG:

American Society of Geriatrics

References

  1. Mounk Y. The Extraordinary Decisions Facing Italian Doctors. The Atlantic. 2020.

  2. Mannelli C. Whose life to save? Scarce resources allocation in the COVID-19 outbreak. J Med Ethics. 2020;46:364–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Rosenbaum L. Facing Covid-19 in Italy—ethics, logistics, and therapeutics on the epidemic’s front line. N Engl J Med. 2020;382:1873–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Sprung CL, Danis M, Iapichino G, Artigas A, Kesecioglu J, Moreno R, et al. Triage of intensive care patients: identifying agreement and controversy. Intensive Care Med. 2013;39:1916–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Berlinger N, Wynia M, Powell T, Micah Hester D, Milliken A, Fabi R, et al. Ethical framework for health care institutions responding to novel coronavirus SARS-CoV-2 (COVID-19). Hast Cent. 2020.

  6. Dzieciatkowski T, Szarpak L, Filipiak KJ, Jaguszewski M, Ladny JR, Smereka J. COVID-19 challenge for modern medicine. Cardiol J. 2020.

  7. Truog RD, Mitchell C, Daley GQ. The toughest triage—allocating ventilators in a pandemic. N Engl J Med. 2020.

  8. Tanzi S, Alquati S, Martucci, De Panfilis L. Learning a palliative care approach during the COVID-19 pandemic: a case study in an Infectious Diseases Unit. Palliat Med. 2020.

  9. Emanuel EJ, Persad G, Upshur R, Thome B, Parker M, Glickman A, Zhang C, Boyle C, Smith M, Phillips JP. Fair allocation of scarce medical resources in the time of Covid-19. N Engl J Med. 2020;382(21):2049–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Committee on Bioethics (DH-BIO). DH-BIO Statement on human rights considerations relevant to the COVID-19 pandemic [Internet]. 2020. https://rm.coe.int/inf-2020-2-statement-covid19-e/16809e2785 (First version 14.4.2020).

  11. UNESCO International Bioethics Committee (IBC), UNESCO World Commission on the Ethics of Scientific Knowledge and Technology (COMEST). Statement on COVD-19: Ethical Considerations from a global perspective. [Internet]. 2020. https://unesdoc.unesco.org/ark:/48223/pf0000373115 (First version 6.4.2020).

  12. Singer PA, Mapa J. Ethics of resource allocation: dimensions for healthcare executives. Hosp Q. 1998.

  13. Matheny Antommaria AH, Gibb TS, McGuire AL, Wolpe PR, Wynia MK, Applewhite MK, et al. Ventilator Triage Policies During the COVID-19 Pandemic at U.S. Hospitals Associated With Members of the Association of Bioethics Program Directors. Ann Intern Med. 2020.

  14. Daugherty Biddison EL, Faden R, Gwon HS, Mareiniss DP, Regenberg AC, Schoch-Spana M, et al. Too Many Patients…A Framework to Guide Statewide Allocation of Scarce Mechanical Ventilation During Disasters. Chest. 2019.

  15. Solomon MZ, Wynia MK, Gostin LO. Covid-19 crisis triage—optimizing health outcomes and disability rights. N Engl J Med. 2020.

  16. McDougall R. Systematic reviews in bioethics: Types, challenges, and value. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy (United Kingdom). 2014.

  17. McCullough LB, Coverdale JH, Chervenak FA. Constructing a systematic review for argument-based clinical ethics literature: The example of concealed medications. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy. 2007.

  18. Gómez-Vírseda C, De Maeseneer Y, Gastmans C. Relational autonomy: What does it mean and how is it used in end-of-life care? A systematic review of argument-based ethics literature. BMC Medical Ethics. 2019.

  19. Dierckx de Casterle B, Gastmans C, Bryon E, Denier Y. QUAGOL: a guide for qualitative data analysis. Int J Nurs Stud. 2012.

  20. European Group on Ethics in Science and New Technologies (EGE). Statement on European Solidarity and the Protection of Fundamental Rights in the COVID-19 Pandemic [Internet]. 2020 p. 1–4. https://ec.europa.eu/info/publications/future-work-future (First version 2.4.2020).

  21. Delmas-goyon P, Hirsch E. COVID-19 CONTRIBUTION FROM THE FRENCH NATIONAL Ethical issues in the face of a pandemic [Internet]. 2020. p. 1–11. https://www.ccne-ethique.fr/sites/default/files/publications/ccne_contribution_march_13_2020.pdf (first version 13.3.2020).

  22. Deutscher Ethikrat. Solidarity and Responsibility during the Coronavirus Crisis [Internet]. 2020. p. 1–8. https://www.ethikrat.org/en/press-releases/2020/solidarity-and-responsibility-during-the-coronavirus-crisis/ (first version 27.3.2020).

  23. Farrell TW, Francis L, Brown T, Ferrante LE, Widera E, Rhodes R, et al. Rationing Limited Health Care Resources in the COVID‐19 Era and Beyond: Ethical Considerations Regarding Older Adults . J Am Geriatr Soc. 2020;

  24. National Bioethics Commitee - Repubblica di San Marino. Answer to the requested urgent opnion on ehtical issues regarding to the use of invasive assisted ventilation in patients all age with serious disabilities in relation to COVID_19 pandemic [Internet]. March 16, 2020. 2020. p. 1–5. http://edf-feph.org/covid19humanrights (first version March 2020).

  25. Conselho Nacional de Etica para as Ciencias da Vida. THE PUBLIC HEALTH EMERGENCY COVID-19 PANDEMIC Statement by the National Council of Ethics for the Life Sciences, Portugal [Internet]. 2020. p. 1–6. https://www.who.int/ethics/topics/outbreaks-emergencies/Statement-CNECV-Covid19_Key-Considerations.pdf?ua=1 (first version April 2020).

  26. Pontifical Academy for Life. Global Pandemic and Universal Brotherhood. Note on the Covid-19 emergency. 2020. p. 1–7.

  27. Nuffield Council on Bioethics. Rapid policy briefing—ethical considerations in responding to the COVID-19 pandemic [Internet]. 2020. p. 1–11. https://www.nuffieldbioethics.org/news/responding-to-the-covid-19-pandemic-ethical-considerations (first version 25.3.2020).

  28. Bioethics Commission. Management of scarce resources in healthcare in the context of the COVID-19 pandemic. Austria; 2020 p. 15 (first version march 2020).

  29. Belgium Society of Intensive Care. Ethical principles concerning proportionality of critical care during the COVID-19 pandemic: advice by the Belgian Society of IC medicine [Internet]. Belgium Society of Intensive Care. 2020. p. 1–4. https://www.hartcentrumhasselt.be/professioneel/nieuws-professioneel/ethical-principles-concerning-proportionality-of-critical-care-during-the-covid-19-pandemic-advice-by-the-belgian-society-of-ic-medicine (first version 26.3.2020).

  30. Ministerio de Sanidad, Gobierno de Espana. Ministry of health report on ethical issues in pandemic situations [Internet]. 2020. https://rm.coe.int/pandemic-covid-19-spain-eng/16809e3a78 (first version 3.4.2020).

  31. UK Department of health and Social Care; Guidance: Responding to COVID-19: the ethical framework for adult social care [Internet]. 2020. https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/covid-19-ethical-framework-for-adult-social-care/responding-to-covid-19-the-ethical-framework-for-adult-social-care (first version 19.3.2020).

  32. Ammer V, Elmet K, Erikson K, Ginter J, Juurik M, Kudeviita M, et al. Recommendations on clinical ethics for Estonian hospitals for distribution of limited health care resources during the COVID-19 pandemic. 2020. p. 10–5. (first version 8.4.2020).

  33. Swiss Academy of Medical Sciences. COVID-19 pandemic: triage for intensive-care treatment under resource scarcity [Internet]. Swiss medical weekly. 2020. p. 1–8. https://www.samw.ch/en/Ethics/Topics-A-to-Z/Intensive-care-medicine.html (first version 7.4.2020).

  34. General Medical Council. Coronavirus: Your frequently asked questions [Internet]. 2020. https://www.gmc-uk.org/ethical-guidance/ethical-hub/covid-19-questions-and-answers#Decision-making-and-consent.

  35. Ireland Department of Health. Ethical Framework for Decision-Making in a Pandemic [Internet]. 2020. p. 1–19. https://www.gov.ie/en/publication/dbf3fb-ethical-framework-for-decision-making-in-a-pandemic/ (first version 24.4.2020).

  36. Vergano M, Bertolini G, Giannini A, Gristina G, Livigni S, Mistraletti G, et al. Raccomandazioni di etica clinica per l’ammissiona a trattamenti intensivi e per la loro sospensione in condizioni eccezionali di squilibrio tra necessità e risorse disponibili. [Internet]. 2020. http://www.siaarti.it/SiteAssets/News/COVID19-documentiSIAARTI/SIAARTI-Covid19-Raccomandazionidieticaclinica.pdf (first version 6.3.2020).

  37. British Medical Association. COVID-19—Ethical Issues. A guidance note [Internet]. 2020. p. 1–9. https://www.bma.org.uk/media/2360/bma-covid-19-ethics-guidance-april-2020.pdf (first version April 2020).

  38. Scottish Government. COVID-19 guidance : ethical advice and support framework [internet]. 3 April. 2020. p. 1–15. https://www.gov.scot/binaries/content/documents/govscot/publications/advice-and-guidance/2020/04/coronavirus-covid-19-ethical-advice-and-support-framework/documents/covid-19-cmo-ethical-advice-and-standards-3-april-2020/covid-19-cmo-ethical-advice-and-sta (first version 3.4.2020).

  39. Royal College of Physicians. Ethical dimensions of COVID-19 for front-line staff [Internet]. 31 March. 2020. p. 1–8. https://www.nhshealthatwork.co.uk/images/library/files/Clinicalexcellence/Ethical_guidance_for_publication_V1_final.pdf (first version 31.3.2020).

  40. V. H. Justice and care: essential reading in feminist ethics. Oxford: Westview press, editor. Oxford; 1995.

  41. Edwards SD. Three versions of an ethics of care. Nurs Philos. 2009.

  42. De Panfilis L, Di Leo S, Peruselli C, Ghirotto L, Tanzi S. “I go into crisis when ...”: ethics of care and moral dilemmas in palliative care. BMC Palliat Care. 2019.

  43. Ehni HJ, Wiesing U, Ranisch R. Saving the most lives—A comparison of European triage guidelines in the context of the COVID-19 pandemic. Bioethics. 2021.

  44. Jeffrey DI. Relational ethical approaches to the COVID-19 pandemic. J Med Ethics. 2020.

  45. Jöbges S, Vinay R, Luyckx VA, Biller-Andorno N. Recommendations on COVID-19 triage: international comparison and ethical analysis. Bioethics. 2020.

  46. Orfali K. Getting to the truth: ethics, trust, and triage in the United States versus Europe during the Covid-19 pandemic. Hastings Cent Rep. 2021.

  47. Sulmasy DP. Dignity and bioethics: history, theory, and selected applications. In: Lanigan T, editor. Human dignity and bioethics. New York: Nova Science Publisher, Inc.; 2008. p. 325–46.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Gürbilek N. Australian health sector emergency response plan for novel coronavirus (COVID-19). J Chem Inf Model. 2013.

  49. University of the Philippines Manila, Covid-19 Ethics Study Group. COVID-19. 2020.

  50. National Bioethics Commission of Mexico. Recommendations regarding the COVID-9 pandemic, from a bioethical approach [Internet]. 2020. https://www.gob.mx/cms/uploads/attachment/file/544828/Recommendations_regarding_the_COVID-19_pandemic__from_a_bioethical_approach__1_.pdf.

  51. Gostin LO, Friedman EA, Wetter SA. Responding to Covid-19: How to Navigate a Public Health Emergency Legally and Ethically. Hastings Cent Rep. 2020.

  52. Curtis JR, Vincent JL. Ethics and end-of-life care for adults in the intensive care unit. The Lancet. 2010.

  53. Sprung CL, Cohen SL, Sjokvist P, Baras M, Bulow HH, Hovilehto S, et al. End-of-Life Practices in European Intensive Care Units: The Ethicus Study. J Am Med Assoc. 2003.

  54. Escher M, Cullati S, Hudelson P, Nendaz M, Ricou B, Perneger T, et al. Admission to intensive care: a qualitative study of triage and its determinants. Health Serv Res. 2019.

  55. Angelos P. Surgeons, ethics, and COVID-19: early lessons learned. J Am Coll Surg. 2020.

  56. Zareifopoulos N, Lagadinou M, Karela A, Karantzogiannis G, Velissaris D. Intubation and mechanical ventilation of patients with COVID-19: what should we tell them? Monaldi Arch Chest Dis. 2020.

  57. Palazzani L. La pandemia CoViD-19 e il dilemma per l’etica quando le risorse sono limitate: chi curare? BiolawJournal-Rivista di Biodiritto. 2020;1:359–70. https://doi.org/10.15168/2284-4503-596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. Auriemma CL, Molinero AM, Houtrow AJ, Persad G, White DB, Halpern SD. Eliminating categorical exclusion criteria in crisis standards of care frameworks. Am J Bioeth. 2020.

  59. White DB, Lo B. A framework for rationing ventilators and critical care beds during the COVID-19 pandemic. JAMA J Am Med Assoc. 2020.

  60. Cesari M, Proietti M. COVID-19 in Italy: ageism and decision making in a pandemic. J Am Med Dir Assoc. 2020.

  61. De Panfilis L, Tanzi S, Costantini M. Il processo decisionale per le cure intensive in situazioni di emergenza: l'etica medica e le cure palliative ai tempi del Covid-19. BiolawJournal-Rivista di Biodiritto. 2020;1:447–51.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Not applicable.

Funding

This research did not receive any specific grant from funding agencies in the public, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

MP: conceptualization, data curation, formal analysis, writing—original draft; LDP: conceptualization, methodology, supervision, writing—original draft; Both authors read and approved the final manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marta Perin.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate

Not applicable.

Consent for publication

Not applicable.

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Supplementary Information

Additional file 1: Appendix 1

. European ethical guidelines developed at the beginning of Covid-19 pandemic.

Additional file 2: Appendix 2

. Conceptual scheme example.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated in a credit line to the data.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Perin, M., De Panfilis, L. Among equity and dignity: an argument-based review of European ethical guidelines under COVID-19. BMC Med Ethics 22, 36 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-021-00603-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-021-00603-9

Keywords