Skip to main content

A bioethical framework to guide the decision-making process in the care of seriously ill patients

Abstract

Background

One of the biggest challenges of practicing medicine in the age of informational technology is how to conciliate the overwhelming amount of medical-scientific information with the multiple patients’ values of modern pluralistic societies. To organize and optimize the the Decision-Making Process (DMP) of seriously ill patient care, we present a framework to be used by Healthcare Providers. The objective is to align Bioethics, Evidence-based Practice and Person-centered Care.

Main body

The framework divides the DMP into four steps, each with a different but complementary focus, goal and ethical principle. Step 1 focuses exclusively on the disease, having accuracy is its ethical principle. It aims at an accurate and probabilistic estimation of prognosis, absolute risk reduction, relative risk reduction and treatments’ burdens. Step 2 focuses on the person, using empathic communication to learn about patient values and what suffering means for the patient. Emphasis is given to learning and active listening, not taking action. Thus, instead beneficence, we trust comprehension and understanding with the suffering of others and respect for others as autonomous moral agents as the ethical principles of Step 2. Step 3 focuses on the healthcare team, having the ethics of situational awareness guiding this step. The goal is, through effective teamwork, to contextualize and link rates and probabilities related to the disease to the learned patient’s values, presenting a summary of which treatments the team considers as acceptable, recommended, potentially inappropriate and futile. Finally, Step 4 focuses on provider-patient relationship, seeking shared Goals of Care (GOC), for the best and worst scenario. Through an ethics of deliberation, it aims for a consensus that could ensure that the patient’s values will be respected as well as a scientifically acceptable medical practice will be provided. In summary: accuracy, comprehension, understanding, situational awareness and deliberation would be the ethical principles guiding each step.

Conclusion

Hopefully, by highlighting and naming the different perspectives of knowledge needed in clinical practice, this framework will be valuable as a practical and educational tool, guiding modern medical professionals through the many challenges of providing high quality person-centered care that is both ethical and evidence based.

Peer Review reports

Background

What is the right thing for providers to do when caring for patients facing a life-threatening illness? In the last 2 decades we’ve witnessed an exponential growth of this answer’s complexity. The big data era adds an overwhelming amount of medical-scientific publications, puzzling the clinician’s capacity to appreciate risks and benefits of treatments. Meanwhile, today’s multicultural societies require new skills from providers to learn and respect the diversity of patient values [1]. Considering the increasing time pressure, it’s not surprising that medical decisions are evermore contentious [2, 3].

As a way to protect themselves and promote autonomy, clinicians sometimes avoid the responsibility of decision-making, and delegate it to patients and surrogates. Such “solitary” autonomy, nevertheless, might inadvertently undermine patient care by depriving patients of the professional guidance needed to make decisions, especially in critical situations [4,5,6]. We believe that the principlism model, based on beneficence, non-maleficence, autonomy and justice, may foster this trend. Facing such controversies at the bedside, physicians are sometimes caught in false dichotomies, as if the solution could be presented in only two excluding answers: autonomy or beneficence. This happens for example in a frequent modern conflict: the disagreement between the Intensive Care Unit (ICU) physician and the oncologist regarding the ICU admission of an advanced cancer patient with an acute deterioration. The intensivist, possibly focused on the high mortality, can disagree with the admission. Meanwhile, the oncologist, possibly concerned about the patient’s fear of death, recommends it. Contemporary ethical reasoning may approach this situation as an autonomy vs. beneficence/maleficence dilemma, where one principle may prevail. Alternatively, providers could even refrain from this difficult discussion and delegate the decision to the patient/surrogate, sometimes by simply asking “what would you like for us to do?” despite the patient/surrogate’s lack of knowledge about the risks and benefits involving each choice. Such ethical dilemmas may arise in other contexts and other diseases, such as Emergency Room or ambulatory settings, involving for instance decisions about whether to start a new course of antibiotics on a patient with advanced dementia or whether to implant a left-ventricular assisted device in a patient with advanced heart failure, among others difficult decisions. We will use the oncologist vs. intensivist dilemma to give a practical perspective of the framework. However, the same framework could also be used in different settings and diseases as well.

To address these challenges, we propose a practical framework to guide the Decision Making Process (DMP) during the care of a seriously ill patient, aiming to align Evidence-Based Practice (EBP) and Person-Centered Care using a bioethical referential.

Main text

The framework

The framework divides the DMP in four steps, each one with a different but complementary goal and ethical principle, as summarized in Table 1.

Table 1 Summary of the Decision-making framework

In practice, the differences between these steps are often unclear and may prompt miscommunication and conflicts. By separating and naming the goal of each step, the framework may foster changing the negotiation focus from positions (to admit or not, to prioritize autonomy or beneficence) to focus on interests [7], potentially reaching a better decision. For example, if an oncologist has a longer relationship with the patient, he may have an optimistic bias about prognosis [8]. The Framework’s first step discusses exclusively the disease, aiming only at accurate probalisitic predictions. In a second step, the intensivist could use comprehension, and learn about the patient’s biography and values. And then, considering EBP and the patient’s values, providers could discuss which treatments would be considered acceptable, which they would recommend, which might be potentially inappropriate and which would be scientifically unacceptable. After expanding the options beyond the yes/no stage, they could involve the patient/surrogate in the DMP towards a consensual goal of care, for example “to attempt to prolong life even if it involves suffering and poor quality of life”, or “to survive, as long as not bed-bound” or “to allow nature to take its course and avoid unnecessary suffering”. Depending on the agreed goal, options could include for example: 1) Full Code ICU admission, or 2) ICU trial of 3–5 days, then reassess and consider Do Not Ressucitate (DNR)/ comfort care if clinical deterioration or 3) DNR/ Do Not Intubate (DNI), comfort care only and no ICU.

The Framework may potentially help to organize the reasoning process. The fundaments of each step are different, but complementary.

First step: Ethics of accuracy, focusing on diseases

Clearly stating this first step of focusing on body and disease can help clinicians to improve accuracy. At the same time, it helps physicians to remember that this is only the first step with more to come.

That being said, despite the medical-scientific development, being accurate in the twenty-first century has become very challenging. The amount of noise in the big data era poses a threat to accuracy. The amount of medical-scientific publications with the word “scientific” has grown from an average of 510 new articles/ year in the early 1900s (personal PUBMED search, Excel file) to an average of 18,703 articles/ year in the first six years of the 2010’s. Anyone wanting to read all the articles on cancer published in 2014 would need to read 400 articles/ day. As Nate Silver puts it, although the amount of information is increasing with amazing speed, the same cannot be said for the amount of useful information. Most of it is just noise, which is increasing faster than the signal [9].

This overwhelming amount of information may cause cognitive discomfort, increasing our trend to a heuristic confirmation, resulting in inaccurate predictions [10]. In a recent systematic review, clinicians more often underestimated rather than overestimated harm, while overestimated rather than underestimated benefits [11]. More than 100 biases and heuristics affecting clinical decision-making have been described [12]. All this noise, heuristics and cognitive bias may contribute to an approach excessively focused on curative or life-prolonging treatment for seriously ill patients even in the last weeks of life [13]. Base rate neglect is possibly the most relevant heuristic threatining accurate predicitons [14]. It happens when details of the narrative lead to making inferences that violate norms of probabilistic reasoning. For example, a narrative of a patient with terminal lung cancer who wishes to survive to care for her children may lead to an excessively optimistic prediction, posing a threat to accuracy, despite its benevolent intention. The discomfort between the cognitions “I think she’ll die soon” and “I don’t want her to die” may be alleviated with the cognition of an overestimated, but inaccurate, prognosis prediction. And this may happen due to base rate neglect- in such case, the base rate may be estimated thorugh the Palliative Performance Index, which would provide the information that most patients in that situation would die within days.

By initially focusing exclusively on the disease and aiming at an accurate prediction in this step, we may separate predictions from desires, reduce cognitive dissonance, minimize bias, and increase accuracy [14, 15]. A classic Kahneman’s method to overcome bias would start with the prediction of the base rate, i.e., first ignoring all the biographical and specific information, prioritizing a macro estimation, i.e., the base rate. Base rate could be prevalence or expected mortality of all cases with similar presentation. Today’s medical scoring systems, based on the analysis of thousands of patients, can offer this information [16]. After this initial estimation, case peculiarities are then used to refine the estimation. In accurate predictions, the order of these events does matter. Keeping it in terms of probability would help physicians to refrain from deterministic thinking (yes/no), developing instead probabilistic reasoning [15].

Probability underlines that prognostication is not a foretelling prophecy but rather it is a factor in risk prediction. Uncertainty is not only admitted as inherent, but openly discussed and estimated [17].

And to make accurate predictions, we have to leave the comfort of confirmation bias and move towards an effort to contemplate disconfirmation. “Why is our hypothesis wrong?” is a more important question than “Why is our hypothesis correct?” [10, 14, 15]. Providers could focus on estimation of prognosis, rates of absolute risk reduction, relative risk reduction, number needed to treat, potential adverse effects and costs and burdens of treatments. Uncertainty might be addressed through estimation of confidence intervals and the disclosure of the potential limitations of generalization of evidence in that specific case.

Thus, the first step is primarily governed by an ethics of accuracy and uses as main tools EBP and probabilistic reasoning.

Second step: Ethics of comprehension and understanding, focusing on the person

An accurate decision about the disease is necessary, but a decision about the disease alone is not enough to define a right decision. A right decision should also include the relief of suffering. However, to do so, the provider should learn about what is suffering for the patient. This requires an understanding attitude, an effort to tolerate listening to the suffering shared by the patient without trying immediately to fix it. Moreover, it requires a method that is not included in natural sciences.

Knowledge of Natural sciences, such as physics or biology, requires an objective knowledge, measurement of its variables and analysis of its relantionships within a theory, using mathematical relationships to explain its efficient causes. Modern natural sciences exclude intentionality and anthropomorphism, substituting the teleological search of “why” for the efficient search of “how”. Moreover, a natural science theory has to be refutable and generalizable. On the other hand, human suffering has a subjective nature, impregnated with cultural meanings, affections and memories, making it difficult to be measured or refutable. Its singular, idiosyncratic nature, cannot be generalized. Suffering is experienced by people, not merely bodies, and has its sources in challenges that threaten the wholeness of individuals as complex social and psychological entities [18]. .And since human suffering is dressed with language, excluding its intentionality would exclude a fundamental part of its nature.

Instead of using natural science to learn about suffering, a human being can use empathic communication to learn about another another human being’s suffering. In clinical practice, natural science methods can provide accurate predictions about the natural course of lung cancer as well as the efficacy of its treatments. However, to reach a right decision, providers should not ignore the influence of the fear of death, the social isolation and financial stress related to loss of functional status and possible spiritual distress that can be manifested in questions such as “What is the meaning of this cancer?”

Thus, the second step explicitly emphatizes the learning about a patient’s biography and values. Values could be defined as “the collection of goals, expectations, predispositions and beliefs that individuals have for certain decisions and their potential outcomes” [19]. Values are meanings amidst a biographical construct, where several narratives take place through a dialectical process. To learn about values and suffering, a provider has to consider wider aspects of the language, for instance, its pitch, accent, rhythm, intonation, called its prosody [20]. Differences in prosody can give almost opposite meanings to the same phrase. “Do you have a problem?” can mean a threat or an offer to help, depending on the prosody. The non-verbal information, the connotation and the socio-cultural referential should be considered as well, since they give meaning to the cognitive and affective aspects from which values are derived.

To learn about patient values, we suggest some guiding questions, asked with empathetic communication techniques adapted both to the providers’ and patient’s coping styles, (Table 2). In this step, emphasis is given to learning and active listening, not acting to find a solution or solve a problem. The challenge for the providers in this step is to be understanding of the patient, to listen and learn about his/ her suffering, with a more contemplative attitude. Perhaps the ethical principle of beneficence (a term which connotes acts of mercy, kindness, and charity) [21], and historically, the ethical basis of the paternalistic medical acts, would not be appropriate. Thus, we trust comprehension and empathy towards the suffering of others and respect for others as autonomous moral agents as the ethical principles of this step.

Table 2 Domains to be explored to understand the patient as a persona

Third step: Ethics of situational awareness, focusing on providers

Third step focuses on improving the clinical judgement of the healthcare team. Clinical judgement can be defined as the exercise of reasoning under uncertainty when caring for patients [22]. It combines Step#1, Step#2 and the context where the stuation is happening. The challenge here is to improve judgement through improvement of situational awareness. The goal is to try to overcome practice based on reflex and adopt practice based on reflection and teamwork.

Situational awareness involves being aware of what is happening in the vicinity to understand how information, events, and one’s own actions will impact goals and objectives, both immediately and in the near future [23, 24]. Specifically, using teamwork communication, providers should contextualize the 1st and 2nd steps, linking rates and probabilities related to the disease to the learned patient’s values. For example, how can we contextualize the knowledge about the most accurate prognostic probabilities regarding a potentially fatal disease and its treatments with the most comprehensive knowledge about the patient’s value on being independent and his/her fears about physical suffering and social isolation? Which decisions would provide the best cost-benefit balance, including the time spent in the treatment? Reflecting upon these questions is central either to EBP or Person-Centered Care. And overconfidence, i.e., a mismatch between perceived and actual performance, may threaten such reflection and decrease teamwork [15].

Nonetheless, improving situational awareness through effective teamwork and feedback can reduce overconfidence [24]. The cognitive aspect of awareness (i.e., “not knowing what you don’t know”) is situation specific. Rarely, the reason for not knowing may be from a lack of knowledge per se, such as seeing a patient with a disease that the physician hasn’t encountered before [10]. More commonly, cognitive errors reflect problems in gathering data, failure to recognize the significance of data or failure to “put it all together.” The cognitive component also includes a failure of metacognition (the willingness and ability to reflect on one’s own thinking processes and to critically examine one’s own assumptions, beliefs, and conclusions). Therefore, teamwork and feedback seeking behavior may reduce overconfidence. It can be fostered by behaviors and attitudes, such as [23]:

  • Using and encouraging self-disclosure, sharing thoughts and feelings related to the situation

  • Practicing and encouraging active listening and openness to feedback from different team members

  • Using assertiveness and constructive criticism, focusing on the team’s best interests rather than individual views only

  • Through effective teamwork, the main goal is to apply the population based scientific evidence while also adapting it to the specific situation of the patient, including the patient’s biology, biography and cultural aspects.

    Moreover, the judgements can be expanded beyond an “all or nothing” model. Through discussions, the team could reach a summary of what the team considers to be:

  1. a)

    The acceptable evidence based treatment, taking into consideration only the scientific view

  2. b)

    The best or recommended treatment following both scientific evidence while also respecting the patient’s biography and wishes.

  3. c)

    The potentially inappropriate treatments following scientific evidence and the patient’s biography and wishes.

  4. d)

    The futile or unacceptable treatments, considering exclusively the scientific basis.

Such approach could broaden the discussion, creating new options by fostering possible solutions considered acceptable. At the same time, it could protect patients and the healthcare system from overtreatment practices resulting from overconfident judgments [24]. For example, in the case of a patient with metastatic lung cancer with septic shock and acute respiratory failure, the team could recommend a) ICU admission for Sepsis treatment and intubation; b) Limited trial of ICU treatment and intubation but transition to comfort care only if no significant improvement in order to respect the patient’s wishes to avoid prolongation of pain and unnecessary suffering; c) recommendation against prolonged ICU admission and tracheostomy (in order to avoid prolonged pain) and d) recommendation for a DNR order since Cardiopulmonary Ressucitation (CPR) would very unlikely offer any benefit in the setting of metastatic cancer.

Fourth step: Ethics of deliberation, focusing on the patient-provider relationship

Last step would focus on patient-provider relationship, seeking shared goals of care (GOC), aligning a medically appropriate treatment with the patient’s valued goals [25]. We consider that GOC should fall within a spectrum between two extremes. At one extreme to maximize any chance of extending life while minimizing unnecessary suffering, and at the other to maximize the relief of suffering while not attempting to artificially prolong life. In between these two extremes, lies a grey area, where the goal could be, for instance, to prolong life as long as no more painful interventions are added. To establish the appropriate GOC, the team would attempt to conciliate the patient’s values and the risks and benefits of interventions. In situations with both a very poor prognosis and a high level of certainty, clinicians could provide an informed assessment and suggest a plan based on the patient’s values [26]. For example, providers could recommend a comfort care approach for the surrogate of an unconscious advanced cancer patient, whose prior known wishes were “not to suffer”. If the surrogate agrees, the team could then place a DNR order. Or, similarly, clinicians can make an informed assent in favor of treatment when there is a very good prognosis and a very high level of certainty (for instance, in a patient with a large pleural effusion the team could recommend in favor of thoracentesis to minimize dyspnea). However, in most real life scenarios, there are many uncertainties about risks and benefits of treatments, also with uncertainties about their impact on the patient’s core values, so the decision about goals of care would require a deliberative dialogue.

Deliberation about GOC is wider than simply asking patients about “what they want” or “if they want to go to the ICU”. Since patients do not necessarily have full understanding to answer such questions, simply asking does not necessarily guarantee autonomy. Within a medical context, decision capacity refers to the abilities needed to utilize information regarding a proposed treatment option to make a congruent choice with one’s own values. It comprehends understanding, expressing a choice, appreciation, and reasoning [27]. Notwithstanding, deliberation about GOC is broader than simply asking what does someone wants. Best practices in discussing GOC include sharing prognostic information, eliciting decision-making preferences, understanding fears and goals, exploring views on trade-offs and impaired function, as well as wishes for family involvement [25, 26]. It is required to empathically inform the patient/surrogate about his/her situation, answer questions, clarify any doubts and acknowledge emotions, accepting that the patient/surrogate requires time to process and “digest” this very difficult information [28, 29]. Moreover, as highlighted since Aristotle, more important than discussing means (in our times, for example, ICU admission) is to discuss ends (for example, try to prolong life regardless of its quality).

The quest for consensus building should guide Step 4. And whenever an effective, efficient and safe medical intervention harms a patient’s core values, causing suffering regarded as intolerable and pointless by a capable patient, we believe that providers should prioritize these values. After all, the ethical imperative of treating a person as a whole is more important than treating just the illness. When no consensus can be reached, the decision could be escalated to the institutional level so that a third party can intermediate the deliberation process. In view of the evidence, consulting a Bioethics Committee might be the best initial step for these situations [30].

Conclusion

This framework could be valuable as a practical and educational tool, guiding modern medical professionals through the many challenges of providing high quality person-centered care that is both ethical and evidence based. It has, however, some limitations. First, the framework has not been validated. It is a conceptual model, based on practice, reflection and expert opinion. Nevertheless, the DMP based on this framework could be tested, to refute our hypothesis or not. Secondly, it could be argued that there is no new information in each step. However, we believe the main strength of this framework is to link several areas of knowledge into a single process, acknowledging the limits and aims of each kind of epistemology forming a practical and didactical tool. Moreover, its steps could be used at separate times or be applied by different professionals. For instance, the first step could be applied by a field expert, or even by a machine with proper input, such as IBM Watson®, generating a standardized report. The second step could be applied by any professional with the ability to communicate with empathy and compassion. Possibly, the third and fourth steps are within the core of the medical profession, and likely couldn’t be replaced by machines or other professionals. Perhaps, the use of DMP frameworks such as the one presented here could aid in maximizing the efficacy and efficiency of the healthcare practice. We understand that this will not be easy nor simple, but, hopefully, it will improve access to healthcare with high quality and ethical standards.

Abbreviations

CPR:

Cardiopulmonary Ressucitation

DMP:

Decision-Making Process

DNI:

Do Not Intubate

DNR:

Do Not Ressucitate

EBP:

Evidence-based practice

GOC:

Goals of care

ICU:

Intensive Care Unit

References

  1. Byram M. Multicultural societies, pluricultural people and the project of intercultural education. Strasbourg: Council of Europe Language Policy Division; 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Schuster RA, Hong SY, Arnold RM, White DB. Investigating conflict in ICUs- is the clinician’s perspective enough? Crit Care Med. 2014;42(2):328–35. https://doi.org/10.1097/CCM.0b013e3182a27598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Piers RD, Azoulay E, Ricou B, DeKeyser GF, Max A, Michalsen A, et al. Appropricus Study Group of the Ethics Section of the European Society of Intensive Care Medicine. Inappropriate care in European ICUs: confronting views from nurses and junior and senior physicians. Chest. 2014;146(2):267–75. https://doi.org/10.1378/chest.14-0256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Stiggelbout AM, Molewijk AC, Otten W, Timmermans DR, van Bockel JH, Kievit J. Ideals of patient autonomy in clinical decision making: a study on the development of a scale to assess patients’ and physicians’ views. J Med Ethics. 2004;30(3):268–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Dzeng E, Colaianni A, Roland M, Chander G, Smith TJ, Kelly MP, et al. Influence of institutional culture and policies on do-not-resuscitate decision making at the end of life. JAMA Intern Med. 2015;175(5):812–9. https://doi.org/10.1001/jamainternmed.2015.0295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Rosenbaum L. The paternalism preference--choosing unshared decision making. N Engl J Med. 2015;373(7):589–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Fisher R, Ury W, Patton B. Getting to yes: negotiation without giving in. 2nd ed. New York: Penguin Group; 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Christakis NA, Lamont EB. Extent and determinants of error in doctors’ prognoses in terminally ill patients: prospective cohort study. BMJ. 2000;320:469–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Silver N. The signal and the noise: the art and science of prediction [e-book]. London: Penguin Books; 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Croskerry P, Norman G. Overconfidence in clinical decision making. Am J Med. 2008;121(5 suppl):s24–9. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.amjmed.2008.02.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Hoffmann TC, Del Mar C. Clinicians’ expectations of the benefits and harm of treatments, screening, and tests: a systematic review. JAMA Intern Med. 2017;177(3):407–19. https://doi.org/10.1001/jamainternmed.2016.8254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Croskerry P. From mindless to mindful practice - cognitive bias and clinical decision making. New Engl J Med. 2013;368(26):2445–8. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJMp1303712.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Cooper Z, Courtwright A, Karlage A, Gawande A, Block S. Pitfalls in communication that lead to nonbeneficial emergency surgery in elderly patients with serious illness: description of the problem and elements of a solution. Ann Surg. 2014;260(6):949–57. https://doi.org/10.1097/SLA.0000000000000721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Kahneman D. Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux; 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Tetlock PE, Gardner D. Superforecasting: the art and science of prediction. London: Penguin Random House; 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Vincent JL, Moreno R. Clinical review: scoring systems in the critically ill. Crit Care. 2010;14(2):207. https://doi.org/10.1186/cc8204. Epub 2010 Mar 26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Simpkin AL, Schwartzstein RM. Tolerating Uncertainty - The Next Medical Revolution? N Engl J Med. 2016;375(18):1713–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Cassel EJ. The nature of suffering and the goals of medicine. N Engl J Med. 1982;306(11):639–45. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJM198203183061104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Guyatt G, Rennie D, Mead M, Cook D, American Medical Association. Users’ guides to the medical literature: a manual for evidence-based clinical practice. 3rd ed. New York: McGraw-Hill Education; 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Kandel ER, Mack S. Principles of neural science. 5th ed. New York: McGraw-Hill Medical; 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Beauchamp T. The Principle of Beneficence in Applied Ethics [First published Wed Jan 2, 2008; substantive revision Thu Oct 3, 2013]. In: Zalta EN, editors. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). Available from: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/principle-beneficence/. Cited 10 Mar 2017.

  22. Redelmeier DA, Ferris LE, Tu JV, Hux JE, Schull MJ. Problems for clinical judgement: introducing cognitive psychology as one more basic science. CMAJ. 2001;164(3):358–60.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Hillson D, Murray-Webster R. Understanding and managing risk attitude. Aldershot: Gower; 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Berner ES, Graber ML. Overconfidence as a cause of diagnostic error in medicine. Am J Med. 2008;121(5 Suppl):S2–23. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.amjmed.2008.01.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Bernacki RE, Block SD. Communication about serious illness care goals: a review and synthesis of best practices. JAMA Intern Med. 2014;174(12):1994–2003. https://doi.org/10.1001/jamainternmed.2014.5271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Curtis JR, White DB. Practical guidance for evidence-based ICU family conferences. Chest. 2008;134(4):835–43. https://doi.org/10.1378/chest.08-0235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Karlawish J, Assessment of decision-making capacity in adults [last updated: Sep 09, 2016]. Available from: https://www.uptodate.com/contents/assessment-of-decision-making-capacity-in-adults?source=search_result&search=decision%20making&selectedTitle=1~150. Cited 25 Feb 2017.

  28. Back A, Arnold RM, Tulsky JA, Fryer-Edwards K, Baile WF. Mastering communication with seriously ill patients : balancing honesty with empathy and hope. New York: Cambridge University Press; 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Jackson VA, Jacobsen J, Greer JA, Pirl WF, Temel JS, Back AL. The cultivation of prognostic awareness through the provision of early palliative care in the ambulatory setting: a communication guide. J Palliat Med. 2013;16(8):894–900.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Aulisio MP, Arnold RM. Role of the ethics committee: helping to address value conflicts or uncertainties. Chest. 2008;134(2):417–24. https://doi.org/10.1378/chest.08-0136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Scheunemann LP, Arnold RM, White DB. The facilitated values history: helping surrogates make authentic decisions for incapacitated patients with advanced illness. Am J Respir Crit Care Med. 2012;186(6):480–6. https://doi.org/10.1164/rccm.201204-0710CP.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Sulmasy DP. Spirituality, religion, and clinical care. Chest. 2009;135(6):1634–42. https://doi.org/10.1378/chest.08-2241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

DNF would like to thank Professors Mia Olsen de Almeida, Daniele Riva and Marcelo Park for their mentoring throughout his career.

All authors would like to thank Julienne Kawai for reviewing the final manuscript for English Grammar and providing insightful feedback.

Funding

Hospital Sírio-Libanês, in Sao Paulo, Brazil, throuaght its Research and Teaching Institute, provided funding to manuscript publication.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

DNF contributed to the manuscript’s conception, design, drafting and critical revision. FK contributed to the manuscript’s drafting and critical revision. CC contributed to the manuscript’s conception and critical revision. All authors read and approved of the final manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Neves Forte.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate

Not applicable. This manuscript does not report on or involve the use of any animal or human data or tissue.

Consent for publication

Not applicable. This manuscript does not contain data from any individual person.

Competing interests

The the authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Forte, D.N., Kawai, F. & Cohen, C. A bioethical framework to guide the decision-making process in the care of seriously ill patients. BMC Med Ethics 19, 78 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-018-0317-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-018-0317-y

Keywords